decoration decoration
Stories

GROKLAW
When you want to know more...
decoration
For layout only
Home
Archives
Site Map
Search
About Groklaw
Awards
Legal Research
Timelines
ApplevSamsung
ApplevSamsung p.2
ArchiveExplorer
Autozone
Bilski
Cases
Cast: Lawyers
Comes v. MS
Contracts/Documents
Courts
DRM
Gordon v MS
GPL
Grokdoc
HTML How To
IPI v RH
IV v. Google
Legal Docs
Lodsys
MS Litigations
MSvB&N
News Picks
Novell v. MS
Novell-MS Deal
ODF/OOXML
OOXML Appeals
OraclevGoogle
Patents
ProjectMonterey
Psystar
Quote Database
Red Hat v SCO
Salus Book
SCEA v Hotz
SCO Appeals
SCO Bankruptcy
SCO Financials
SCO Overview
SCO v IBM
SCO v Novell
SCO:Soup2Nuts
SCOsource
Sean Daly
Software Patents
Switch to Linux
Transcripts
Unix Books

Gear

Groklaw Gear

Click here to send an email to the editor of this weblog.


You won't find me on Facebook


Donate

Donate Paypal


No Legal Advice

The information on Groklaw is not intended to constitute legal advice. While Mark is a lawyer and he has asked other lawyers and law students to contribute articles, all of these articles are offered to help educate, not to provide specific legal advice. They are not your lawyers.

Here's Groklaw's comments policy.


What's New

STORIES
No new stories

COMMENTS last 48 hrs
No new comments


Sponsors

Hosting:
hosted by ibiblio

On servers donated to ibiblio by AMD.

Webmaster
1 right, 2 oh, so wrong | 188 comments | Create New Account
Comments belong to whoever posts them. Please notify us of inappropriate comments.
Correction: 97 -> 70 -n/t.
Authored by: macliam on Tuesday, March 26 2013 @ 03:47 AM EDT
.

[ Reply to This | Parent | # ]

You can't make bricks without straw
Authored by: Ian Al on Tuesday, March 26 2013 @ 04:43 AM EDT
The courts have declared that computers work in ways that they do not. PolR explains in Does Programming a Computer Make A New Machine? that the addition of software to a general purpose computer does not change the machine and does not improve the function of the machine and is thus not a patentable invention according to §101.

Mayo says:
Section 101 of the Patent Act defines patentable subject matter. It says (excluding citations):

“Whoever invents or discovers any new and useful process, machine, manufacture, or composition of matter, or any new and useful improvement thereof, may obtain a patent therefor, subject to the conditions and requirements of this title.” 35 U. S. C. §101.

The Court has long held that this provision contains an important implicit exception. “[L]aws of nature, natural phenomena, and abstract ideas” are not patentable. Diamond v. Diehr, ; see also Bilski v. Kappos; Diamond v. Chakrabarty; Le Roy v. Tatham (1853); O’Reilly v. Morse(1854); cf. Neilson v. Harford, Webster’s Patent Cases 295, 371 (1841) (English case discussing same). Thus, the Court has written that “a new mineral discovered in the earth or a new plant found in the wild is not patentable subject matter.

Likewise, Einstein could not patent his celebrated law that E=mc2; nor could Newton have patented the law of gravity. Such discoveries are ‘manifestations of . . . nature, free to all men and reserved exclusively to none.’ ” Chakrabarty (quoting Funk Brothers Seed Co. v. Kalo Inoculant Co.(1948)).

“Phenomena of nature, though just discovered, mental processes, and abstract intellectual concepts are not patentable, as they are the basic tools of scientific and technological work.” Gottschalk v. Benson (1972). And monopolization of those tools through the grant of a patent might tend to impede innovation more than it would tend to promote it.

The Court has recognized, however, that too broad an interpretation of this exclusionary principle could eviscerate patent law. For all inventions at some level embody, use, reflect, rest upon, or apply laws of nature, natural phenomena, or abstract ideas.

Thus, in Diehr the Court pointed out that “ ‘a process is not unpatentable simply because it contains a law of nature or a mathematical algorithm.’ ” (quoting Parker v. Flook (1978)). It added that “an application of a law of nature or mathematical formula to a known structure or process may well be deserving of patent protection.” (Diehr). And it emphasized Justice Stone’s similar observation in Mackay Radio & Telegraph Co. v. Radio Corp. of America (1939):

“ ‘While a scientific truth, or the mathematical ex pression of it, is not a patentable invention, a novel and useful structure created with the aid of knowledge of scientific truth may be.’ ” (quoting Mackay Radio). See also Funk Brothers (“If there is to be invention from [a discovery of a law of nature], it must come from the application of the law of nature to a new and useful end”). Still, as the Court has also made clear, to transform an unpatentable law of nature into a patent-eligible application of such a law, one must do more than simply state the law of nature while adding the words “apply it.” See, e.g., Benson.
Forgive the extensive quote. It makes some very useful points. Take the last sentence. Using the judicial exclusion of 'abstract ideas' in place of 'laws of nature', continuations can be seen as patenting abstract ideas and saying anyone who 'applies them' is infringing on the patented abstract idea.

Please also note that the use of math in processes is only valid in a patent as part of the whole process and there must be significant postprocess activity (Bilski, Diehr, Flook). The math is not protected in any other process. Also, there must be an innovative concept in the process taken as a whole. From Flook (without references in citations):
Even though a phenomenon of nature or mathematical formula may be well known, an inventive application of the principle may be patented. Conversely, the discovery of such a phenomenon cannot support a patent unless there is some other inventive concept in its application.

Here it is absolutely clear that respondent's application contains no claim of patentable invention. The chemical processes involved in catalytic conversion of hydrocarbons are well known, as are the practice of monitoring the chemical process variables, the use of alarm limits to trigger alarms, the notion that alarm limit values must be recomputed and readjusted, and the use of computers for "automatic monitoring-alarming."

Respondent's application simply provides a new and presumably better method for calculating alarm limit values. If we assume that that method was also known, as we must under the reasoning in Morse, then respondent's claim is, in effect, comparable to a claim that the formula 2(pi)r can be usefully applied in determining the circumference of a wheel.

As the Court of Customs and Patent Appeals has explained, "if a claim is directed essentially to a method of calculating, using a mathematical formula, even if the solution is for a specific purpose, the claimed method is nonstatutory." In re Richman (1977).
The inclusion of math as a 'component' of a machine invention or an improvement to a machine is judicially excluded by the above quote from Mayo. This is because the addition of math to a machine does not change the machine. The function of the machine is not improved. Improving the function of a computer machine by using it in a better way (e.g. by using another program) is not patentable according to §101.

The Supreme Court did not explain how they came to the conclusion that the patented inventions in Benson, Flook and Bilski were abstract ideas. They refuse to exclude, say, business processes and software as a whole and just refer to the cornerstone cases as a guide. This suggests that they will not accept any scientific opinion on abstract ideas to exclude classes of abstract ideas or to identify the patenting of abstract ideas.

In Bilski they said:
It is important to emphasize that the Court today is not commenting on the patentability of any particular invention, let alone holding that any of the above-mentioned technologies from the Information Age should or should not receive patent protection.

This Age puts the possibility of innovation in the hands of more people and raises new difficulties for the patent law. With ever more people trying to innovate and thus seeking patent protections for their inventions, the patent law faces a great challenge in striking the balance between protecting inventors and not granting monopolies over procedures that others would discover by independent, creative application of general principles. Nothing in this opinion should be read to take a position on where that balance ought to be struck.
Since PolR has shown that computers only work to manipulate symbols by executing software algorithms (i.e. a process) then the social science of semiotics shows that the result of that manipulation only has meaning to people as an interpretant. Diehr, Flook and Benson tell us that a process must have significant postprocess activity (i.e. a change in a referent such as the production of precision rubber components) to meet §101. In other words, a process or method must produce a referent to be patentable. As a machine, a computer with a program only produces manipulated symbols which can be presented on a display. That display is how human beings perceive the interpretants. Putting ideas in peoples' minds is non-statutory subject matter (See, Flook, above).

---
Regards
Ian Al
Software Patents: It's the disclosed functions in the patent, stupid!

[ Reply to This | Parent | # ]

  • tl;dr - Authored by: Anonymous on Tuesday, March 26 2013 @ 09:11 AM EDT
Diehr
Authored by: macliam on Tuesday, March 26 2013 @ 01:58 PM EDT

The Supreme Court cabined Diehr very neatly in Mayo:

The Court pointed out that the basic mathematical equation, like a law of nature, was not patentable. But it found the overall process patent eligible because of the way the additional steps of the process integrated the equation into the process as a whole. Those steps included “installing rubber in a press, closing the mold, constantly determining the temperature of the mold, constantly recalculating the appropriate cure time through the use of the formula and a digital computer, and automatically opening the press at the proper time.“ Id., at 187, 101 S.Ct. 1048. It nowhere suggested that all these steps, or at least the combination of those steps, were in context obvious, already in use, or purely conventional. And so the patentees did not “seek to pre-empt the use of [the] equation,” but sought “only to foreclose from others the use of that equation in conjunction with all of the other steps in their claimed process.” Ibid. These other steps apparently added to the formula something that in terms of patent law's objectives had significance—they transformed the process into an inventive application of the formula.

The subtext seems to be that Justice Breyer doesn't really think that constantly monitoring the temperature and opening the press in Diehr really added enough, but it was apparently good enough for the majority in Diehr, and that is all that matters.

Justice Breyer is careful not to ‘dissect the claim’: “And they insist that a process that focuses upon the use of a natural law also contain other elements or a combination of elements, sometimes referred to as an ‘inventive concept,’ sufficient to ensure that the patent in practice amounts to significantly more than a patent upon the natural law itself.” (emphasis added). So the proscription against ‘claim dissection’ in Diehr is still good law.

But there was quite a bit of obiter dicta in Diehr on pages 189 to 191, which Justice Rehnquist was parroting from Judge Rich, establishing the Three Doors doctrine in Supreme Court jurisprudence. Did Justice Breyer mention or analyse this argument in Mayo? Did any justice write separately to discuss these dicta in Diehr, either to support them or to refute them? Well, much further on in Mayo:

Third, the Government argues that virtually any step beyond a statement of a law of nature itself should transform an unpatentable law of nature into a potentially patentable application sufficient to satisfy § 101's demands. Brief for United States as Amicus Curiae. The Government does not necessarily believe that claims that (like the claims before us) extend just minimally beyond a law of nature should receive patents. But in its view, other statutory provisions—those that insist that a claimed process be novel, 35 U.S.C. § 102, that it not be ‘obvious in light of prior art,‘ § 103, and that it be ‘full[y], clear[ly], concise[ly], and exact[ly]’ described, § 112—can perform this screening function. In particular, it argues that these claims likely fail for lack of novelty under § 102.

This approach, however, would make the ‘law of nature’ exception to § 101 patentability a dead letter. The approach is therefore not consistent with prior law. The relevant cases rest their holdings upon section 101, not later sections. Bilski, 561 U.S. ___, 130 S.Ct. 3218, 177 L.Ed.2d 792; Diehr, supra; Flook, supra; Benson, 409 U.S. 63, 93 S.Ct. 253, 34 L.Ed.2d 273. See also H.R.Rep. No. 1923, 82d Cong., 2d Sess., 6 (1952) (‘A person may have 'invented' a machine or a manufacture, which may include anything under the sun that is made by man, but it is not necessarily patentable under section 101 unless the conditions of the title are fulfilled‘ (emphasis added)).

Justice Breyer even had the chutzpah to list Diehr itself in his list of cases!

Thus all those dicta in Diehr about § 101 being purely about whether the claim recited eligible subject-matter were effectively overruled sub silentio! Judge Rich must have been spinning in his grave!

So, now that the Supreme Court in Mayo have framed Diehr as a case where the industrial process added enough, why is Groklaw, instead of taking a hint from the Supreme Court and letting sleeping dogs lie, putting forth a massive discursive diffuse discussion document, full of theory of computation, semiotics and metaphysics, whose only concluding legal argument is to observe that, under Groklaw's proposed text, the invention in Diehr was patent-eligible because the claim cited a referent?

It seems to me that the Supreme Court has moved on from the old metaphysical ‘a programmed computer is a particular machine and thus patent-eligible!’ / ‘software is math and therefore patent-ineligible’ argument that has been aired repeated before, without apparently inducing anyone to change their mind, and I really think that Groklaw would do better to take the hint and move on also. (But of course, Groklaw is PJ's blog, so it is up to her where she takes it.)

How I think, or at least hope, that the Supreme Court will frame the argument, when they finally get a computer-related case properly before them, is as follows: ‘Abstract ideas, abstract intellectual concepts, and methods that can in principle be performed purely in the mind or with pencil and paper are not patentable. In the 21st century, merely implementing such a process on a computer is not enough to confer patentability.’ And if they do this, all those old arguments about the patentability of mathematical algorithms will lose all their relevance.

(And the Supreme Court GVR'ed Wildtangent v. Ultramercial for reconsideration by the Federal Circuit in the light of Mayo, so they certainly recognize the connection between obvious applications of laws of nature and obvious applications of abstract ideas.)

[ Reply to This | Parent | # ]

1 right, 2 oh, so wrong
Authored by: Imaginos1892 on Tuesday, March 26 2013 @ 05:31 PM EDT
Of course the computer is a machine.

But it can never be "programmed in a way that adds functionality
to the computer". A computer is a machine for running programs,
and is inherently capable of running any program within the limits
of its capacity. Any program is simply data, or media presented
to the computer in the correct format. It is not a "process, machine,
manufacture, or composition of matter"; it is a DESCRIPTION or
DEFINITION of a process expressed as a sequence of simple digital
logic operations in a form suitable to be performed by the computer
but which can be performed by any agent capable of accurately
evaluating the operations. No program can alter the computer in
any way.

Would you claim that a movie projector is "transformed into a new
machine" by putting film into it? A different, separately patentable
machine for each film? That would be no more absurd than what
you are trying to claim for the computer and a program.

Yes, the computer is a finite state machine, but within its limits
it is a useful approximation of an infinite state machine and
operates by exactly the same principles. You are either trying
to confuse the issue, or are yourself confused.
----------------------
Simple answers to complex questions are always wrong.

[ Reply to This | Parent | # ]

Groklaw © Copyright 2003-2013 Pamela Jones.
All trademarks and copyrights on this page are owned by their respective owners.
Comments are owned by the individual posters.

PJ's articles are licensed under a Creative Commons License. ( Details )