decoration decoration
Stories

GROKLAW
When you want to know more...
decoration
For layout only
Home
Archives
Site Map
Search
About Groklaw
Awards
Legal Research
Timelines
ApplevSamsung
ApplevSamsung p.2
ArchiveExplorer
Autozone
Bilski
Cases
Cast: Lawyers
Comes v. MS
Contracts/Documents
Courts
DRM
Gordon v MS
GPL
Grokdoc
HTML How To
IPI v RH
IV v. Google
Legal Docs
Lodsys
MS Litigations
MSvB&N
News Picks
Novell v. MS
Novell-MS Deal
ODF/OOXML
OOXML Appeals
OraclevGoogle
Patents
ProjectMonterey
Psystar
Quote Database
Red Hat v SCO
Salus Book
SCEA v Hotz
SCO Appeals
SCO Bankruptcy
SCO Financials
SCO Overview
SCO v IBM
SCO v Novell
SCO:Soup2Nuts
SCOsource
Sean Daly
Software Patents
Switch to Linux
Transcripts
Unix Books

Gear

Groklaw Gear

Click here to send an email to the editor of this weblog.


You won't find me on Facebook


Donate

Donate Paypal


No Legal Advice

The information on Groklaw is not intended to constitute legal advice. While Mark is a lawyer and he has asked other lawyers and law students to contribute articles, all of these articles are offered to help educate, not to provide specific legal advice. They are not your lawyers.

Here's Groklaw's comments policy.


What's New

STORIES
No new stories

COMMENTS last 48 hrs
No new comments


Sponsors

Hosting:
hosted by ibiblio

On servers donated to ibiblio by AMD.

Webmaster
Logical Processes, and observations on 'bright line' tests | 179 comments | Create New Account
Comments belong to whoever posts them. Please notify us of inappropriate comments.
Logical Processes, and observations on 'bright line' tests
Authored by: macliam on Sunday, March 17 2013 @ 07:00 AM EDT

I intended 'logical' to be interpreted in a sense related to logic, specifically formal logic, and indeed classical first order logic. Most of the theorems of mathematics could in principle be represented as theorems in first order logic following from the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms. I would suggest that what the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms add to first order logic is a set of basic principles for handling infinite sets, such as the sets of integers and real numbers. Thus classical logic and predicate calculus represent principles that are even more fundamental than mathematics per se, though mathematicians would probably consider them a subset of mathematics. I cannot think of any adjective other than logical that could serve the process of indicating the fundamental nature of the principles involved.

In any case, there is no prospect of anything like this being put to district judges and juries to interpret. The Supreme Court made it plain that the judicial exceptions are for "laws of nature", "natural phenomena" and "abstract ideas" (and possibly "products of nature" as decided in the forthcoming Myriad case), and that they are not minded to extend this list by further exceptions for "business methods" and, by extension, "mathematical algorithms" and the like. Moreover neither the "machine or transformation" test nor any other sort of bright-line dispositive test is acceptable for determining whether or not a claimed invention falls within these categories of excluded subject matter. At most, such tests are "useful clues" or "investigative tools".

If the analysis of the nature of computer-related processes has relevance then the relevance surely lies in attempting to clarify the issues involved. And if something useful emerges, it may form a good basis for legal briefs to the Supreme Court or Federal Circuit. The printing press example is a particularly good one. But if part of the purpose were to devise a dispositive test that judges and juries could use in order to determine whether or not a claimed invention is patent-eligible, then that exercise would be misconceived as contradicting the letter and spirit of the Supreme Court judgement in Bilski v. Kappos. As the PTO have told the Federal Circuit, such "bright line" tests not grounded in the wording of the statute are not in themselves acceptable as a means of separating patent-eligible and patent-ineligible subject matter.

And any tests will be determined by the Federal Circuit through case law, as and when they come to terms with the principles set out by the Supreme Court and develop their jurisprudence in accordince with principles set out in Bilski. Mayo, the forthcoming Myriad case that is currently being briefed before the Supreme Court, and probably some future computer-related case, maybe arising out of CLS v. Alice or Ultramercial v. Wildtangent or any other of the cases currently before the Federal Circuit relating to patent-eligibility of computer-related subject matter under Section 101 of the patent act. And the Patent Office and judges and juries will then follow whatever principles and procedures that the Federal Circuit establishes.

In particular, suppose that the following were proposed as a definitive bright-line test:

Claims reciting software will be patentable when they claim a referent which is a patent-eligible invention.

Then it is surely a sitting duck for patent attorneys who will gleefully set about writing patent applications on fundamental ideas and basic principles that are filled with claims to "referents that are patent-eligible inventions" but that neverthess less in practice claim masses of routine everyday activity "widely practised within the art" or prempt most if not all useful applications of scientific discoveries and mathematical breakthroughs. Don't underestimate the ingenuity of patent attorneys when they draft claims that fall within acknowledged "safe harbors"!

[ Reply to This | Parent | # ]

Groklaw © Copyright 2003-2013 Pamela Jones.
All trademarks and copyrights on this page are owned by their respective owners.
Comments are owned by the individual posters.

PJ's articles are licensed under a Creative Commons License. ( Details )