decoration decoration
Stories

GROKLAW
When you want to know more...
decoration
For layout only
Home
Archives
Site Map
Search
About Groklaw
Awards
Legal Research
Timelines
ApplevSamsung
ApplevSamsung p.2
ArchiveExplorer
Autozone
Bilski
Cases
Cast: Lawyers
Comes v. MS
Contracts/Documents
Courts
DRM
Gordon v MS
GPL
Grokdoc
HTML How To
IPI v RH
IV v. Google
Legal Docs
Lodsys
MS Litigations
MSvB&N
News Picks
Novell v. MS
Novell-MS Deal
ODF/OOXML
OOXML Appeals
OraclevGoogle
Patents
ProjectMonterey
Psystar
Quote Database
Red Hat v SCO
Salus Book
SCEA v Hotz
SCO Appeals
SCO Bankruptcy
SCO Financials
SCO Overview
SCO v IBM
SCO v Novell
SCO:Soup2Nuts
SCOsource
Sean Daly
Software Patents
Switch to Linux
Transcripts
Unix Books

Gear

Groklaw Gear

Click here to send an email to the editor of this weblog.


You won't find me on Facebook


Donate

Donate Paypal


No Legal Advice

The information on Groklaw is not intended to constitute legal advice. While Mark is a lawyer and he has asked other lawyers and law students to contribute articles, all of these articles are offered to help educate, not to provide specific legal advice. They are not your lawyers.

Here's Groklaw's comments policy.


What's New

STORIES
No new stories

COMMENTS last 48 hrs
No new comments


Sponsors

Hosting:
hosted by ibiblio

On servers donated to ibiblio by AMD.

Webmaster
"attached to it" link 404 | 216 comments | Create New Account
Comments belong to whoever posts them. Please notify us of inappropriate comments.
s/1515/n1515/; also s/1518/n1518/
Authored by: Anonymous on Tuesday, July 31 2012 @ 04:05 PM EDT
That is, we've lost a couple of <BR>'s or </P>'s or something in
the HTML at those points! (Christenson)

[ Reply to This | Parent | # ]

"attached to it" link 404
Authored by: gfim on Wednesday, August 01 2012 @ 12:22 AM EDT
The link to http://groklawstatic.ibiblio.org/pdf3/ApplevSamsung-1491-Ex1.pdf in the last
paragraph of the article "attached to it" responds with "We're
sorry, but we can't find the page you have requested."

---
Graham

[ Reply to This | Parent | # ]

that isn't an Apple => that it isn't an Apple
Authored by: Anonymous on Wednesday, August 01 2012 @ 08:05 AM EDT
And that's why, as Williams reports, the Samsung attorney is telling the jury
that people know when they are buying a Samsung tablet or phone that it isn't an
Apple product.

[ Reply to This | Parent | # ]

HP faces billion ... -> Oracle faces
Authored by: Anonymous on Wednesday, August 01 2012 @ 07:39 PM EDT
HP faces billion dollar bill from Oracle title of news picks, should be :

Oracle faces billion dollar bill from HP

[ Reply to This | Parent | # ]

"Trade Dress" != "Product Design"
Authored by: Anonymous on Wednesday, August 01 2012 @ 10:36 PM EDT
You were correct to cite Two Pesos regarding trade dress protection under the Lanham Act, and the Cornell LII definition you quoted is quite helpful as well, but you left out a very important piece of the issue. The most important part of the Cornell quote, in this context, is that "The Lanham Act protects trade dress if it serves the same source-identifying function as a trademark." There's a lot of meaning hidden in that condition, which I'll try to unpack.

Under US trademark law, there are two ways that something can serve as the identifier of the source of goods or services*, and thus be treated as a trademark: it can be "inherently distinctive," which means that it would be considered as a source-identifier even by a consumer who has had no previous exposure to it; or else it must show "acquired distinctiveness" (also, less helpfully, called "secondary meaning"), which means that consumers have been trained, through repeated exposure, to consider it as a source-identifier. The most common way to demonstrate acquired distinctiveness (because it's specifically allowed by statute) is to provide "proof of substantially exclusive and continuous use thereof as a mark by the applicant in commerce for the five years before the date on which the claim of distinctiveness is made."

Among word marks, those that are "arbitrary" (KODAK is the classic example), "fanciful" (e.g., APPLE for a record company), or "suggestive" (e.g., GREYHOUND for a bus company) can have inherent distinctiveness and gain federal protection from the instant they're first used in commerce; a "descriptive" name (e.g., FAST for a bus company) would need to earn acquired distinctiveness before becoming protected as a trademark. A "generic" mark (e.g., BUS COMPANY for a bus company), however, is categorically ineligible for trademark protection. (For more on these categories of marks, see page *9 of Abercr ombie & Fitch v. Hunting World.)

Of course, it's not just words that can serve the "source-identifying function" referred to above. As the Supreme Court put it in Quali tex v. Jacobson Products, when it held that colors, though not inherently distinctive, can acquire distinctiveness (sorry for the long quote):

The Lanham Act gives a seller or producer the exclusive right to "register" a trademark, 15 U. S. C. § 1052, and to prevent his or her competitors from using that trademark, § 1114(1). Both the language of the Act and the basic underlying principles of trademark law would seem to include color within the universe of things that can qualify as a trademark. The language of the Lanham Act describes that universe in the broadest of terms. It says that trademarks "includ[e] any word, name, symbol, or device, or any combination thereof." § 1127. Since human beings might use as a "symbol" or "device" almost anything at all that is capable of carrying meaning, this language, read literally, is not restrictive. The courts and the Patent and Trademark Office have authorized for use as a mark a particular shape (of a Coca-Cola bottle), a particular sound (of NBC's three chimes), and even a particular scent (of plumeria blossoms on sewing thread). If a shape, a sound, and a fragrance can act as symbols why, one might ask, can a color not do the same?

A color is also capable of satisfying the more important part of the statutory definition of a trademark, which requires that a person "us[e]" or "inten[d] to use" the mark

"to identify and distinguish his or her goods, including a unique product, from those manufactured or sold by others and to indicate the source of the goods, even if that source is unknown." 15 U. S. C. § 1127.

True, a product's color is unlike "fanciful," "arbitrary," or "suggestive" words or designs, which almost automatically tell a customer that they refer to a brand. Abercrombie & Fitch Co. v. Hunting World, Inc., 537 F. 2d 4, 9-10 (CA2 1976) (Friendly, J.); see Two Pesos, Inc. v. Taco Cabana, Inc., 505 U. S. 763, 768 (1992). The imaginary word "Suntost," or the words "Suntost Marmalade," on a jar of orange jam immediately would signal a brand or a product "source"; the jam's orange color does not do so. But, over time, customers may come to treat a particular color on a product or its packaging (say, a color that in context seems unusual, such as pink on a firm's insulating material or red on the head of a large industrial bolt) as signifying a brand. And, if so, that color would have come to identify and distinguish the goods—i. e., "to indicate" their "source"—much in the way that descriptive words on a product (say, "Trim" on nail clippers or "Car-Freshner" on deodorizer) can come to indicate a product's origin.

The key holding of Two Pesos, meanwhile, is that for trade dress, "proof of secondary meaning is not required to prevail on a claim under § 43(a) of the Lanham Act where the trade dress at issue is inherently distinctive." The necessary implication is that, unlike a color, trade dress can be inherently distinctive.

Alright; so what; why am I making a big deal of this? Because the shape of the iPhone isn't "trade dress." Eight years after Two Pesos, the Supreme Court decided Wal-M art v. Samara Brothers, where it noted that "trade dress" is "a category that originally included only the packaging, or 'dressing,' of a product, but in recent years has been expanded . . . to encompass the design of a product." After giving a brief overview of inherent vs acquired distinctiveness, and deciding that product design is at least in principle capable of serving as a trademark, the opinion gets to the real meat of the holding (again, sorry for the length of the quote):

Nothing in [the Lanham Act] demands the conclusion that every category of mark necessarily includes some marks "by which the goods of the applicant may be distinguished from the goods of others" without secondary meaning—that in every category some marks are inherently distinctive.

Indeed, with respect to at least one category of mark— colors—we have held that no mark can ever be inherently distinctive. In Qualitex, petitioner manufactured and sold green-gold dry-cleaning press pads. After respondent began selling pads of a similar color, petitioner brought suit under § 43(a), then added a claim under § 32 after obtaining registration for the color of its pads. We held that a color could be protected as a trademark, but only upon a showing of secondary meaning. . . .

It seems to us that design, like color, is not inherently distinctive. The attribution of inherent distinctiveness to certain categories of word marks and product packaging derives from the fact that the very purpose of attaching a particular word to a product, or encasing it in a distinctive packaging, is most often to identify the source of the product. Although the words and packaging can serve subsidiary functions—a suggestive word mark (such as "Tide" for laundry detergent), for instance, may invoke positive connotations in the consumer's mind, and a garish form of packaging (such as Tide's squat, brightly decorated plastic bottles for its liquid laundry detergent) may attract an otherwise indifferent consumer's attention on a crowded store shelf—their predominant function remains source identification. Consumers are therefore predisposed to regard those symbols as indication of the producer, which is why such symbols "almost automatically tell a customer that they refer to a brand," and "immediately . . . signal a brand or a product `source.'" And where it is not reasonable to assume consumer predisposition to take an affixed word or packaging as indication of source—where, for example, the affixed word is descriptive of the product ("Tasty" bread) or of a geographic origin ("Georgia" peaches)—inherent distinctiveness will not be found. That is why the statute generally excludes, from those word marks that can be registered as inherently distinctive, words that are "merely descriptive" of the goods, § 2(e)(1), 15 U. S. C. § 1052(e)(1), or "primarily geographically descriptive of them," see § 2(e)(2), 15 U. S. C. § 1052(e)(2). In the case of product design, as in the case of color, we think consumer predisposition to equate the feature with the source does not exist. Consumers are aware of the reality that, almost invariably, even the most unusual of product designs—such as a cocktail shaker shaped like a penguin—is intended not to identify the source, but to render the product itself more useful or more appealing.

The fact that product design almost invariably serves purposes other than source identification not only renders inherent distinctiveness problematic; it also renders application of an inherent-distinctiveness principle more harmful to other consumer interests. Consumers should not be deprived of the benefits of competition with regard to the utilitarian and esthetic purposes that product design ordinarily serves by a rule of law that facilitates plausible threats of suit against new entrants based upon alleged inherent distinctiveness. . . .

Respondent contends that our decision in Two Pesos forecloses a conclusion that product-design trade dress can never be inherently distinctive. . . . Two Pesos unquestionably establishes the legal principle that trade dress can be inherently distinctive, but it does not establish that product-design trade dress can be. Two Pesos is inapposite to our holding here because the trade dress at issue, the décor of a restaurant, seems to us not to constitute product design. It was either product packaging—which, as we have discussed, normally is taken by the consumer to indicate origin—or else some tertium quid that is akin to product packaging and has no bearing on the present case.

The shape of a smartphone certainly seems to me to be more an issue of product design than packaging/dress. That being the case, if Apple wants to rely on the Lanham Act to protect the shape of the iPhone, it will have to prove acquired distinctiveness, because Two Pesos and the possibility of inherent distinctiveness simply do not apply.

Please note that I am only commenting about the general state of the law around trade dress and product design. I haven't read the briefs in this case; I don't know what evidence is being offered; I don't know whether Apple has managed to produce evidence of acquired distinctiveness and convinced the Patent and Trademark Office to issue it a trademark registration for the shape of the iPhone. Also, please note that infringement of a design patent is a separate cause of action from infringement of a product design used as a trademark, and I'm only talking about the latter.

* I am omitting discussion of other kinds of mark (e.g., certification marks) for simplicity. If you know what they are, you probably didn't need this explanation in the first place.

[ Reply to This | Parent | # ]

Groklaw © Copyright 2003-2013 Pamela Jones.
All trademarks and copyrights on this page are owned by their respective owners.
Comments are owned by the individual posters.

PJ's articles are licensed under a Creative Commons License. ( Details )