decoration decoration
Stories

GROKLAW
When you want to know more...
decoration
For layout only
Home
Archives
Site Map
Search
About Groklaw
Awards
Legal Research
Timelines
ApplevSamsung
ApplevSamsung p.2
ArchiveExplorer
Autozone
Bilski
Cases
Cast: Lawyers
Comes v. MS
Contracts/Documents
Courts
DRM
Gordon v MS
GPL
Grokdoc
HTML How To
IPI v RH
IV v. Google
Legal Docs
Lodsys
MS Litigations
MSvB&N
News Picks
Novell v. MS
Novell-MS Deal
ODF/OOXML
OOXML Appeals
OraclevGoogle
Patents
ProjectMonterey
Psystar
Quote Database
Red Hat v SCO
Salus Book
SCEA v Hotz
SCO Appeals
SCO Bankruptcy
SCO Financials
SCO Overview
SCO v IBM
SCO v Novell
SCO:Soup2Nuts
SCOsource
Sean Daly
Software Patents
Switch to Linux
Transcripts
Unix Books

Gear

Groklaw Gear

Click here to send an email to the editor of this weblog.


To read comments to this article, go here
Groklaw's Proposed Response to the USPTO's Request for Suggested Topics for Future Discussion - Care to Help? ~pj
Sunday, March 10 2013 @ 08:43 PM EDT

Here's Groklaw's proposed response to the USPTO's request for suggested topics for discussion in the future by the Software Partnership, as it calls it. Thank you for your input, everyone. But please take a look at the result. We tried to incorporate everything that would strengthen the draft. This was a group project by the membership at Groklaw, and now we'd appreciate feedback from the world, before we send it off on Friday.

We came up with four topics for future discussion. You may think of others. Because we have to file this on Friday, and that means if you want to contribute a thought, please do it by Wednesday.

We are also publishing a more detailed supplement on those four topics, explaining in depth why we propose those four topics, providing some foundation and providing resources. This we will not sent to the USPTO, but it is referenced in the document we will send, if they wish to read more. If you think my decision on that is flawed, let me know. But all they asked for is topics. If we overwhelm them with a lot of what they didn't ask for, I worry that it would be counterproductive. The USPTO will be publishing the comments they receive, and so both documents will be available to the world, and people can read it or not based on their interest level, which is part of the purpose. I would particularly appreciate your help with the supplement.

Jump To Comments

[Suggested Topics ]

[The Supplement]

First, here's the document we will send to the USPTO, the list of the four proposed topics for discussions, after which you'll find the supplement. Feel free to comment on either document:

Response to the USPTO on the Second Topic:
Suggested Additional Topics for Future Discussion by the Software Partnership

In response to the USPTO's request for topics for future discussion by the Software Partnership, the technical community at Groklaw suggests the following four topics, in order of priority:
1: Is computer software properly patentable subject matter?

2: Are software patents helping or hurting innovation and the US economy?

3: How can software developers help the USPTO understand how computers actually work, so issued patents match technical realities, avoiding patents on functions that are obvious to those skilled in the art, as well as avoiding duplication of prior art?

4: What is an abstract idea in software and how do *expressions* of ideas differ from *applications* of ideas?

In order to explain why these topics could be fruitful, here are some brief thoughts in explanation.

Suggested topic 1:
Is computer software properly patentable subject matter?

If software consists of two elements neither of which is patentable subject matter, can software itself by patentable subject matter? Software consists of algorithms, in other words mathematics, and data, which is being manipulated by the algorithms. Mathematics is not patentable subject matter and neither is data. On what basis, then, is software patentable subject matter? We would welcome a discussion on this topic, as it is a key issue to the developer community. Note that Groklaw has published a number of articles on this topic, which can be found at http://www.groklaw.net/staticpages/index.php?page=Patents2

A particular point of interest is how the meaning of data influences the patentable subject matter analysis. Computers manipulate bits, and bits are electronic symbols which are used to convey meaning. In some patents, like in Diehr's industrial process for curing rubber, what this meaning signifies is actually claimed clearly. But in most pure software patents the meaning is merely referred to. Should this distinction influence whether the claim is patentable?

Suggested topic 2:
Are software patents helping or hurting the US innovation and hence the economy?

It would be useful to hear from entrepreneurs on a wide scale on the effects software patents are having on their startups or business projects. Microsoft's Bill Gates himself has stated that if software patents had been allowed when he was starting his business, he would have been blocked.1a Is that happening to today's entrepreneurs? If software authors are unable to clear all rights to their own products because there is no practical way to do so, how can that foster progress and innovation? Rather it seems to force developer, or the companies that hire them, to choose between developing innovative products with the certainty that if it is successful, there will be infringement lawsuits, or stop developing.

Every firm with an internal IT department writes software. Every firm which maintains it own website writes software. There are roughly 634,000 firms in the United States with 20 or more employees. While not all of these firms produce software, many of the 1.7 million firms with 5 to 19 employees do. In an ideal world, all firms should verify all patents as they are issued to avoid infringement. This is a constant on-going activity because corporate software must frequently be adapted to new needs and all new versions may potentially infringe a patent. A study has concluded the task is mathematically impossible to accomplish.2a

Even if a patent lawyer only needed to look at a patent for 10 minutes, on average, to determine whether any part of a particular firm's software infringed it, it would require roughly 2 million patent attorneys, working full-time, to compare every firm's products with every patent issued in a given year.

This is a mathematical impossibility because there are only roughly 40,000 registered patent attorneys and patent agents in the US.

This estimation covers just the work of keeping up with the newly issued patents every year. Checking already issued patents would require more attorneys.

This result follows from simple arithmetic. Suppose we assume that 40,000 patents are issued per year, 600,000 firms actively write software, resulting in approximately 2000 billable hours per attorney per year. Then the math is straightforward: 40,000 patents*600,000 firms*(10 minutes per patent-firm pair)/(2000*60 minutes per attorney)=2 million attorneys.

Compare lines of code with sentences in a book. Each English sentence expresses an idea. Each combination of sentences expresses a more complex idea. Then more and more complex ideas are expressed into paragraphs, chapters etc. The total number of ideas from all works of authorship is extremely large. Imagine an hypothetical intellectual property regime where all such ideas are patentable. This would generate a large number of patents. All authors must check all patents for potential infringement. It simply is not possible to do so.

It is impossible to promote innovation with a system where the authors of software have no way to verify they own all rights to their own work. Such a system is guaranteed to harm the economy with monopolistic rent-seeking and unneeded litigation.

Suggested topic 3:
How can software developers help the USPTO understand how computers actually work, so issued patents match technical realities, avoiding patents on functions that are obvious to those skilled in the art, as well as avoiding duplication of prior art?

The current interpretation of patent law is plagued with what developers view as erroneous conceptions of how computers work. Other than the current USPTO request for input, developers feel shut out of decisions, and yet they are the very ones who understand what software is and how it does what it does.

Textbooks describe in detail what mathematical algorithms are, but no one seems to understand or to reference these sources. Instead, we see courts using standard dictionaries, and the result is confusion about what algorithms are. An unrealistic distinction between so-called mathematical algorithms and those that purportedly are not mathematical has been the result. Since this impacts the controversy of when a computer-implemented invention is directed to a patent-ineligible abstract idea, it's a serious omission.

Second, it seems some, including some courts, believe the functions of software are performed through the physical properties of electrical circuits, incorrectly treating the computer as a device which operates solely through the laws of physics. This approach is factually and technically incorrect because not everything in software functions through the laws of physics. Bits are symbols, and they have meanings. The meaning of bits is essential to performing the functions of software. The capability of bits to convey meaning is not a physical property of the computer.

Software developers don't write software by working with the physical properties of circuits. Developers define the meaning of data and implement operations of arithmetic and logic that apply to the meaning. They debug software by reading the meaning of the data stored in the computer and verifying whether the correct operations are performed. The aspects of software related to meaning cannot be explained solely in terms of the physical properties of the computer.

This erroneous physical view of the computer is the basis of an oft-stated argument. Some claim that software alters the computer it runs on. This is used to justify the view that software patents are actually a subcategory of hardware patents. But to demonstrate what is wrong with that argument, let's compare a printing press with a computer.

It is easy to see that the contents of a book is not a machine part. The meaning of a book is not explained by the laws of physics applicable to a printing press. But the comparison with a computer shows that there is no material difference in their handling of meaning. Any argument applicable to a printing press is applicable to a computer and vice-versa.

Imagine a claim on a printing press configured to print a specific book, say Tolkien's Lord of the Ring. This is a claim on a machine which operates according to the laws of physics. Printing is a physical process for laying ink on paper. It functions without the intervention of a human mind. But still this process involves the meaning of a book. The claim is infringed only if the book has the recited meaning.

We may argue that a configured printing press is physically different from an unconfigured one. The configured printing press can print a book while the unconfigured one cannot. Books with different contents are different articles of manufacture. Differently configured printing presses perform different functions because they make different articles of manufacture. Therefore, as this hypothetical argument goes, a printing press configured to print a specific book is a specific machine which performs a specific practical and useful task.

Software patents are often written similarly to this analogy. Like a printing press, the computer operates according to the laws of physics. It functions mostly without the intervention of the human mind, although from time to time human input may be required. But the process of computing needs the meaning of the data to actually solve problems. The claim is infringed only if the data has the recited meaning.

The standard argument that a programmed computer is different from an unprogrammed one is exactly symmetric to the one we have just made about printing presses. There is a reason for this. The technologies are not that different. A computer connected to a printer can be configured to print a book. Also modern printing presses may be controlled by embedded computers.

There is no material difference between a configured printing press and a programmed computer in their handling of meaning. Users of a computer read the meaning of outputs. They also enter the inputs based on the meaning. When programming a computer, programmers must define the meaning of data. They implement algorithms which perform operations of arithmetic and logic on the meaning of this data. When debugging, programmers must inspect the internals of the computer to determine whether the correct operations are being performed. This requires reading the contents of computer memory and verifying it has the expected meaning. In other words, the act of making the invention depends on defining and reading the data stored in the computer. Software works only if the data has the correct meaning.

The output of a printing process is a book. Different books are distinguished by their contents. A typographer must define and verify the contents of the information to be printed to configure the printing press correctly. In other words, the act of making the invention depends on defining and reading the data stored in the printing press. A printing press works precisely because it prints the right contents. Printing makes a physical book which can be read and sold. Books with different contents are different books. A wrongly configured printing press prints the wrong book. Therefore the utility of the printing press doesn't depend just on the laws of physics. It also depends on the contents of the book.

Both machines work in part according to the laws of physics and in part through operations of meaning.

The courts have failed to acknowledge the role of meaning in software. Some errors result from the failure to take into consideration the descriptions of what is a mathematical algorithm in mathematical literature. Other errors result from explicitly and incorrectly denying the role of symbols and meaning in computers. And more errors result from the belief that computers operate solely through the physical properties of electrical circuits.

Imagine now that every time a printing press prints a new book, you could patent that printing press as a new machine because it printed a new book. That is exactly what patent law does with software, purporting to create a new machine because new software running on the computer supposedly creates a new machine. And yet the computer, like a printing press, can run any software at all that you can devise, just as a printing press can print any book you write.

No one would allow a patent on a previously existing printing press just because it is now configured to print a new novel. Yet that is exactly what is allowed with software.

The consequence is a proliferation of patents on the expressions of ideas.

Suggested topic 4:
What is an abstract idea in software and how do expressions of ideas differ from applications of ideas?

Abstract is not synonymous with vague or overly broad. A mathematical algorithm is narrowly defined with great precision, but still it is abstract.

Abstract is not the opposite of useful. The ordinary procedure for carrying an addition is a mathematical algorithm. It has a lot of practical uses in accounting, engineering and other disciplines. But still it is abstract. In particular it is designed to handle numbers arbitrarily large no matter whether we have the practical means of writing down all the digits. Besides, there are useful abstract ideas outside of mathematics. For example the contents of a reference manual such as a dictionary is both abstract and useful.

Mathematics is abstract in part because it studies infinite structures. For example, the series of natural numbers 0, 1, 2, ... cannot exist in the concrete universe, because it is infinite. Also, symbols in a mathematical sense are abstract entities distinct from the marks on paper or their electronic equivalent. For example, there are infinitely many decimals of pi even though there is no practical way to write them down. Infinity guarantees that mathematics is abstract. Therefore a definition of "abstract ideas" must acknowledge the abstractness of mathematics.

A proper understanding of the role of meaning is key to understanding when a claim is directed to a patent-ineligible abstract idea in software. Software patents don't claim abstract ideas directly. They claim them indirectly through the use of a physical device to represent them by means of bits. It would be easier to recognize claims on patent-ineligible abstract ideas if it were understood they take the form of claims on expressions of ideas as opposed to applications of ideas. The bits are symbols and the computation is a manipulation of the symbols. Expressions of ideas occur through this use of symbols.

This suggests a test similar to the printed matter doctrine. This test is best described using the concepts and vocabulary of a social science called semiotics. This science studies signs, entities which are used to stand for something else.

Computers should be recognized to be what semioticians call sign-vehicles, physical devices which are used to represent signs. The sign itself is an abstraction represented by the sign-vehicle. Hence, sign-vehicles and signs are distinct entities.

In semiotics the triadic notion of a sign distinguishes between two types of meaning. There is the actual worldly thing denoted by the sign. This is called the referent. And there is the idea of that thing a human being would derive from reading the sign. This is called an interpretant. A sign usually conveys both types of meanings simultaneously. An example might be a painting representing a pipe. The painting itself is a sign-vehicle. People seeing this painting will think of a pipe. This thought is an interpretant. An actual pipe is a referent.

If nothing has been invented but thoughts in the mind of human beings, we should not be able to claim a sign-vehicle expressing these ideas as if they were applications of the ideas. But when the real thing denoted by the expression is claimed, we may have a patentable invention. For example a mathematical calculation for curing rubber standing alone is not patentable under this test. It is just numbers letting a human think about how rubber should be cured. But when the actual rubber is cured the referent is recited and the overall process taken as a whole may be patentable. These ideas lead to this test.

A claim is directed to a patent-ineligible abstract idea when there is no nonobvious advances over the prior art outside of the interpretants. A claim is written to an application of the idea when the referent is claimed instead of merely referred to.

This test is technology-neutral. It is applicable precisely when the claimed invention is a sign, or when it is a machine or process for making a sign. It applies whether the invention is software, hardware or some yet to be invented technology. This test works without having to define the boundary between what is software and what isn't.

The concepts of semiotics are quite simple and easy to define. They are related to the dichotomy between ideas and expression of ideas in copyright law. Therefore this test for abstract ideas helps clarify the line between what should be protected with copyrights and what belongs to patent law. The expressions of interpretants may be protected by copyrights and the corresponding referents may be protected by patents.

This test will correctly identify abstract mathematical ideas. Mathematics is, among other things, a written language. It has a syntax and a meaning which are defined in textbooks on topics such as mathematical logic. Algorithms in the mathematical sense are features of this language. They are procedures for manipulating symbols. They solve problems because they implement operations of arithmetic and logic on the meaning of the symbols. Algorithms are also procedures which are suitable for machine implementation. Computer programs may solve a problem only if it is amenable to an algorithmic solution. In this sense, all software executes a mathematical algorithm.

Mathematical language refers to abstract mathematical entities such as numbers, geometric shapes, etc. We assimilate this abstract meaning with interpretants. Mathematical language may also be used to describe things in the concrete world, for instance using laws of physics. The corresponding referents are applications of mathematics. Mathematical algorithms and other types of mathematical subject matter are a subcategory of interpretants. And things in the concrete world modeled using mathematical language are a subcategory of referents. Hence the proposed test will properly distinguish between the expression of a mathematical idea from an application of the same idea. Claims of applications are accepted while claims on expressions are rejected.

Groklaw has published this document here, along with a more detailed explanation, with references, on why we believe these four topics could be fruitful topics for discussion.

__________
1a Gates exact words were:

"If people had understood how patents would be granted when most of today's ideas were invented, and had taken out patents, the industry would be at a complete standstill today."
"Challenges and Strategy" (16 May 1991). Also from: http://bat8.inria.fr/~lang/reperes/ local/Challenges.and.Strategy

2a See Mulligan, Christina and Lee, Timothy B., Scaling the Patent System (March 6, 2012). NYU Annual Survey of American Law, Forthcoming. Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract_id=2016968. The quoted paragraph is at pages 16-17.

And here is the more detailed explanation, the supplement. And this is where I really need your help. I didn't write it, although I've tried to organize it, but I'm still editing it to try to make it a little more conversational, so if you see errors or shades of meaning that are slightly off, please say so:

Supplement to the Response to the USPTO on the Second Topic
Detailed Explanations on the Proposed Topics
by Groklaw

The patent system should distinguish the expression of an abstract idea from an application of an idea. Currently the distinction between the two is not correctly made in the legal analysis of software patents. Expressions of ideas are being mistaken for applications and are patented as a result. This makes it confusing to try to define what is a claim directed to patent-ineligible abstract ideas.

Because of this confusion, innovation is not being promoted as intended. When expressions of ideas are patented, none of the assumptions underlying the operating principles of the patent system are true. Therefore the expected benefits of patents are not realized.

Recognizing that an expression is not an application would make it possible for the patent system to be able to recognize claims directed to abstract ideas and a major source of problems with software patents would be corrected.

A. Factual Background

Let's begin by defining some important terms and summarizing some fundamental facts about computers, software, and the underlying mathematical principles.1

1. Semiotics defines the concepts and vocabulary necessary to understand issues of meaning.

In the social science of semiotics, a thing that stands for something else is called a sign. Books and computers when associated with their meanings are examples of signs. Semiotics defines the concepts and vocabulary we need to properly analyze meaning. We present here the basic concepts which will be used in the rest of this response.

A sign in the Piercean tradition has three elements. The physical object used to represent the sign is called a sign-vehicle. The entity in the world which is denoted by the sign is called the referent. The idea a human being would form of the meaning of the sign is called an interpretant. This triadic view of a sign is traditionally represented as a triangle.

We may use the famous painting The Treachery of Images as an illustration of these notions. This painting represents a pipe with the legend "Ceci n'est pas une pipe" which means "This is not a pipe" in French. The point is that a painting of a pipe is a representation of a pipe. It is not the pipe itself. In this example, the painting is the sign-vehicle, the actual pipe is the referent, and the idea of a pipe in the human mind is the interpretant.

We have a sign when there is a convention on how to associate the sign-vehicle with its meaning. In the case of the painting this convention is the practice of associating a visual representation of something with what is represented.

Please note how the sign-vehicle is only an element of a sign. It is not the whole sign. The three elements must be brought together in order to have a sign. A human interpreter with the knowledge of the convention will mentally assemble the three elements and "make the sign" by associating the sign-vehicle with its meaning. This is a cognitive process of the human mind called semiosis. In particular, books and computers when taken as physical objects independently of their meanings are sign-vehicles. They are not the whole signs because semantical elements are not physical parts of books and computers. These sign-vehicles are turned into signs by semiosis when a human interpreter read meanings into them.

2. Mathematics is a written language based on logic and algorithms are procedures for manipulating symbols in this language.

Mathematics is a written language. We can find the definition of its syntax and semantics in textbooks on the foundations of mathematics, especially mathematical logic.2 There is more to mathematics than the language. Mathematical entities like numbers and geometrical figures are also mathematics. But for the purpose of this discussion it is the linguistic aspect that matters most. Concepts such as formulas, equations and algorithms are part of this mathematical language.

A mathematical formula is text written with symbols in this mathematical language. It is the equivalent of a sentence in English. An equation is a special kind of formula which asserts that two mathematical expressions refer to the same value.

The famous equation E=mc2 is an example of such a mathematical formula. The meaning of this formula is a is a law of nature, actually a law of physics. It is a statement relating the mass of an object at rest with how much energy there is in this object. This shows how mathematical language may be used to describe the real world.

The formula implies a procedure to compute the energy when the mass is known. Here it is:

  1. Multiply the speed of light c by itself to obtain its square c2.

  2. Multiply the mass m by the value of c2 obtained in step 1.

  3. The result of step 2 is the energy E.

This kind of procedure is known in mathematics as an algorithm. The formula is not the algorithm. This procedure is the algorithm. Someone with sufficient skills in mathematics will know the algorithm simply by looking at the formula. This is why it is often sufficient to state a formula when we want to state an algorithm.

The task of carrying out the algorithm is called a computation. When carrying out the algorithm with pencil and paper we have to write mathematical symbols, mostly digits representing numbers but also other symbols such as the decimal point. These writings too are parts of mathematical language. In the example, the meaning of the writings are numbers representing the speed of light, its square, the mass and the energy of an object.

A function is not an algorithm.

Mathematicians distinguish between a function and an algorithm. Hartley Rogers explains:3 (emphasis in the original)

It is, of course, important to distinguish between the notion of algorithm, i.e., procedure, and the notion of function computable by algorithm, i.e., mapping yielded by procedure. The same function may have several different algorithms.

A mathematical function is a correspondence between one or more input values and a corresponding output value. For example the function of doubling a number associates 1 with 2, 2 with 4, 3 with 6 etc. Nonnumerical functions also exists.

A function is not a process. There is no requirement that the function must be computed in a specific manner. All methods of computation which produce the same output from the same input compute the same function.

Despite the similarly sounding words, a software function is not the same thing as a mathematical function. However the two concepts are closely related. If we look at the underlying principles of mathematics which are at the foundations of computer science the functions of software are described with mathematical functions.4 The methods used to perform the functions of software are implemented using mathematical algorithms.

The language of mathematics is based on logic

There is a close connection between logic and mathematics. Theorems are proven by means of deductions where the formulas and expressions in mathematical language are organized according to the rules of logic. Most mathematical truth are established in this manner.

The relationship between mathematics and logic is explained by Haskell Curry as follows:5 (emphasis in the original, footnote omitted)

The first sense is that intended when we say that "logic is the analysis and criticism of thought." We observe that we reason, in the sense that we draw conclusions from our data; that sometimes these conclusions are correct, sometimes not; and that sometimes these errors are explained by the fact that some of our data were mistaken, but not always; and gradually we become aware that reasonings conducted according to certain norms can be depended on if the data are correct. The study of these norms, or principles of valid reasoning, has always been regarded as a branch of philosophy. In order to distinguish logic in this sense from other senses introduced later, we shall call it philosophical logic.

In the study of philosophical logic it has been found fruitful to use mathematical methods, i.e., to construct mathematical systems having some connection therewith. What such system is, and the nature of the connection, are question which will concern us later. The systems so created are naturally a proper subject for study in themselves, and it is customary to apply the term 'logic' to such a study. Logic in this sense is a branch of mathematics. To distinguish it from other senses, it will be called mathematical logic.

[A]lthough the distinction between the different senses of 'logic' has been stressed here as a means of clarifying our thinking, it would be a mistake to suppose that philosophical and mathematical logic are completely separate subjects. Actually, there is unity between them. mathematical logic, as has been said, is fruitful as a means of studying philosophical logic. Any sharp line between the two aspects would be arbitrary.

Finally, mathematical logic has a peculiar relation to the rest of mathematics. For mathematics is a deductive science, at least in the sense that a concept of rigorous proof is fundamental to all parts of it. The question of what constitutes a rigorous proof is a logical question in the sense of the preceding discussion. The question therefore falls within the province of logic; since it is relevant to mathematics, it is expedient to consider it in mathematical logic. Thus the task of explaining the nature of mathematical rigor falls to mathematical logic, and indeed may be regarded as its most essential problem. We understand this task as including the explanation of mathematical truth and the nature of mathematics generally. We express this by saying that mathematical logic includes the study of the foundations of mathematics.

Mathematical logic is also part of the mathematical underpinnings of computer science.5

To summarize the main points, mathematics is a written language. It has a syntax and a semantics. It is used to establish theorems by means of logical proofs. Formulas and equations are expressions in this language. Computations and algorithms are elements of this language which are used to solve problems.

3. Mathematicians have defined their requirements for a procedure to be accepted as a mathematical algorithm.

If we seek a definition in the sense of a short dictionary-like description of an algorithm we won't find one which is universally accepted. But if we read textbooks of computation theory and mathematical logic we find full text descriptions of what it takes for a procedure to be a mathematical algorithm. These descriptions vary in their choice of words and some authors mention aspects others omit. It is best to read a few of them to obtain a complete picture.

Here are the collection of requirements for a procedure to be an algorithm which are mentioned by one or another of the authors cited in the footnote.6

Procedures to actually solve a category of problems

An algorithm is a procedure intended to actually solve a category of problems. It takes one of more inputs describing the specific problem and it produces the corresponding solution. This means the procedure is meant to be carried out, at least in principle if not in practice. If it is followed without error it will produce the correct answer. Stoltenberg-Hansen, Lindström and Griffor explain:7 (emphasis in the original)

An algorithm for a class K of problems is a method or procedure which can be described in a finite way (a finite set of instructions) and which can be followed by someone or something to yield a computation solving each problem in K.

Mathematicians sometimes call algorithms "effective procedures". This concept is broadly defined in intuitive terms because it is intended to be open ended. Researchers constantly discover new ways of defining and carrying out procedures able to actually solve problems. Their notion of algorithm isn't strictly defined because they don't want to exclude from the concept these future discoveries. When they need mathematical rigor mathematicians study specific models of computations like Turing machines, recursive functions or λ-calculus.

Manipulation of symbols

All algorithms are ultimately procedures for manipulating symbols. Stoltenberg-Hansen, Lindström and Griffor explain:8 (emphasis in the original)

It is reasonable to assume, by the intended meaning of an algorithm explained above, that each problem in K should be a concrete or finite object. We say that an object is finite if it can be specified using finitely many symbols in some formal language.

Sometimes we encounter a discussion of algorithms which presumes the computations are about numbers. For a mathematician the two concepts of arithmetic and symbolic computations are equivalent.

Boolos, Burgess and Jeffrey explain one aspect of this equivalence by pointing our that ultimately numbers must be represented by means of symbols when doing arithmetic calculations:9 (emphasis in the original, link added)

When we are given as argument a number n or pair of numbers (m, n), what we in fact are directly given is a numeral for n or an ordered pair of numerals for m and n. Likewise, if the value of the function we are trying to compute is a number, what our computations in fact end with is a numeral for that number. Now in the course of human history a great many systems of numeration have been developed, from the primitive monadic or tally notation, in which the number n is represented by a sequence of n strokes, through systems like Roman numerals, in which bunches of five, ten, fifty, one-hundred, and so forth strokes are abbreviated by special symbols, to the Hindu-Arabic or decimal notation in common use today.

Conversely, the same authors explains that symbols may be represented as numbers. Then symbolic computations may be defined in terms of arithmetical calculations:10 (emphasis in the original, link added)

A necessary preliminary to applying our work on computability, which pertained to functions on natural numbers, to logic, where the object of study are expressions of a formal language, is to code expressions by numbers. Such a coding of expressions is called a Gödel numbering. One can then go on to code finite sequences of expressions and still more complicated objects.

This may sound as a chicken and egg problem. Which is defined first? The manipulation of symbols or the manipulation of numbers? Actually is is impossible to manipulate numbers directly without first representing them as symbols of some sort. Even when a computation is defined as an operation of arithmetic it is ultimately a manipulation of symbols.

Finite description

An algorithm must be described with a finite number of symbols.11 It is not possible to learn and execute an procedure whose description is infinite. This requirement may seem obvious but much of mathematics is about infinite structures, like the set of natural numbers or the decimal expansion of pi. Mathematicians felt the need to set this boundary for themselves.

Precise definition

The steps must be defined precisely so we know exactly how to execute them. Boolos, Burgess and Jeffrey describe this requirement as follows:12

The instruction must be completely definite and explicit. They should tell you at each step what to do, not tell you to go ask someone else what to do, or to figure out for yourself what to do: the instructions should require no external source of information, and should require no ingenuity to execute, so that one might hope to automate the process of applying the rules, and have it performed by some mechanical device.

Actual execution

A procedure doesn't solve a problem unless and until it is actually executed. The requirements finite description and precise definition are meant to instruct exactly how the procedure should be executed.13

This requirement of actual execution has a consequence. An algorithm imposes a burden on the computing agent that executes it. The steps must be actually carried out and the symbols must be actually written. This burden is called computational complexity. It is measured by the number of steps which must be executed and by the amount of writing space required to write the symbols. This burden typically vary according to the size of the inputs. When the number of symbols in the inputs is larger the number of steps and the storage space required to read and process the inputs will also increase.

Independence from physical limitations

Mathematicians assume the agent executing the algorithm has unlimited time to carryout the computation and unlimited space to write symbols while computing. The goal is to separate the mathematical properties of the algorithm from the physical resources available to compute. Boolos, Burgess and Jeffrey describe this requirement as follows:14 (emphasis in the original)

There remains the fact that for all but a finite number of values of n, it will be infeasible in practice for any human being, or any mechanical device, actually to carry out the computation: in principle it could be completed in a finite amount of time if we stayed in good health so long, or the machine stayed in working order so long; but in practice we will die, or the machine will collapse, long before the process is complete. (There is also a worry about finding enough space to store the intermediate results of the computation, and even a worry about finding enough matter to use in writing down these results: there is only a finite amount of paper in the world, so you'd have to writer [sic] smaller and smaller without limit; to get an infinite number of symbols down on paper, eventually you'd be trying to write on molecules, on atoms, on electrons.) But our present study will ignore these practical limitations, and work with an idealized notion of computability that goes beyond what actual people or actual machines can be sure of doing. Our eventual goal will be to prove that certain functions are not computable, even if practical limitations on time, speed and amount of material could somehow be overcome, and for this purpose the essential requirement is that our notion of computability not be too narrow.
It is understood that an algorithm will be carried out in practice by a computing agent with finite amount of time and writing space, therefore the computation can only be done for a "finite number of values of n" as Boolos and al. put it. This doesn't mean the calculation isn't done according to the algorithm. It means that the algorithm is carried out only to the extent that sufficient resources are available. When the resources are exhausted the calculation stops prematurely and the answer is not reached.

For example consider the ordinary pencil and paper procedure of arithmetic for adding numbers. It is designed to produce the correct answer no matter how many digits are required to write the numbers. If the numbers have one trillion digits it may not be realistic to expect a live human to complete the task. Mathematicians still regard this procedure as a mathematically correct algorithm for addition. They consider that finding a computer powerful enough to carry out the task until completion is a separate issue from finding a mathematically correct procedure.

The purpose of this abstraction is to study the mathematical properties of the computation in itself, independently from the limitations of the computing agent. For example mathematicians want to know when a function cannot be computed at all regardless of the physical resources available. And they want to be confident that the algorithm produces the correct answer for all inputs. This procedure gives us a mathematical guarantee that an increase of the capabilities of the hardware will increase the range of computations which are practical without introducing errors because the algorithm is not limited to the capabilities of the current hardware.

Termination

This requirement is controversial.15 In some flavors of 'algorithm' it is omitted.

People who expect the algorithm to actually produce the answer demand that there is a point in time where the answer is available. This means there must be a finite number of steps after which the procedure is completed and the answer is available. But there are useful computational procedures which cannot meet this requirement. Stoltenberg-Hansen, Lindström and Griffor explain:16 (emphasis in the original)

The requirement that an algorithm should solve each problem in a class K is actually a requirement on the class K (to be algorithmically decidable) rather than on the concept of an algorithm. Indeed the notion of an algorithm is partial by its very nature. Regarding an algorithm as a finite set of instructions, there is certainly no a priori reason to expect the computation, obtained from applying the algorithm to a particular problem, to terminate.

An example is a procedure for computing the decimals of pi. This calculation can never be carried out until the end because there are infinitely many decimals. On the other hand it can compute the decimals of pi to an arbitrary degree of precision if we have the patience to carry it out long enough.

The main mathematical models of computation17 have the ability to define both algorithms which terminate and computational procedures which don't terminate.

Deterministic execution

This requirement is controversial.18 In some flavors of 'algorithm' it is omitted.

Some people expect the requirement of precise definition to imply that every step be deterministic, with no random element. But there are useful computational procedures that involve probabilistic steps, that is some steps have an outcome randomly selected from a predefined set of possibilities. This is called a randomized algorithm.

It is well know that a randomized algorithm can be transformed into a deterministic algorithm when a source of random numbers is available as an input. Then the random element is moved out of the calculation to the source of input. The calculation itself is deterministic relative to the input. Alternatively, pseudo-random number generators may be used to simulate nondeterminism by deterministic means.

4. Algorithms are machine-implementable because they rely only on syntax to be executed, but they solve problems because they implement operations of arithmetic and logic on the meaning of the data.
The requirement of precise definition permits the machine execution of algorithms. See the preceding quote of Boolos et al. An alternative statement of this requirement is given by Stephen Kleene as follows:19

In performing the steps we have only to follow the instructions mechanically, like robots; no insight or ingenuity or intervention is required of us.

If the meanings of the symbols are ambiguous it is impossible to execute the algorithm in this manner. Resolving the ambiguity is an intervention that requires insight or ingenuity. This requirement would not be met. On the other hand if the symbols are unambiguous, for purposes of executing an algorithm mechanically, like robots, their meanings are superfluous. For example, when evaluating a single bit there is no need for the step of noticing the symbol means the boolean value true when we already know the symbol is the numeral 1 because this numeral always means true in boolean context.

For the sake of comparison, here is an example of a procedure which is not an algorithm: Interim Examination Instructions For Evaluating Subject Matter Eligibility Under 35 U.S.C. § 101 (PDF). Legal procedures such as this one require the human to consider the meaning of the information and then inject additional information based on his experience, knowledge, and convictions to reach a decision. They require a lot of insight and ingenuity to be executed and for this reason they are not mathematical algorithms.

A consequence of this requirement is that the algorithm operates only on the syntax of the mathematical language. It doesn't operate on the meaning. This point has been noticed by Richard Epstein and Walter Carnielli20, where they describe a series of models of computations used to define classes of algorithms:21

What all of these formalizations have in common is that they are all purely syntactical despite the often anthropomorphic descriptions. They are methods for pushing symbols around.

Human beings may be taught procedures to process data based on their meanings. Computers can't. They must be programmed to execute algorithms. This is a prerequisite for writing a machine executable program. If the procedure is not an algorithm it is not possible to program a computer for it.

But then what is the role of meaning? It defines the problem and its solution. There is a whole body of computation theory which analyzes computation from the point of view syntactic manipulations of symbols. But this literature is limited in the study of which problems are solved by these algorithms. For that we need the meaning.

The art of the programmer is to find an algorithm which corresponds to operations of arithmetic and logic that solves the problem. As a first step the programmer must define how the data elements will be representing symbolically, with bits.22 This task is referred to with phrases such as: defining a data model, defining data structures and defining data formats. This task amounts to defining how to represent the problem and its solution in a suitable language of symbols. Then as a second step the programmer must find an algorithm operating on this data that will produce the correct outputs. This means the programmer must find a way to manipulate the symbols without referring to their meanings and still reach the correct answer. If the programmer fails to to find such a procedure he cannot write a machine executable program.

The connection between logic and data is key. Well chosen logical inferences can solve practical problems. They can be turned into algorithm using data types. Consider the following series of statements.

  1. "Abraham Lincoln" is a character string.
  2. "Abraham Lincoln" is the name of a human being.
  3. "Abraham Lincoln" is the name of a politician.
  4. "Abraham Lincoln" is the name of a president of the United States of America.

Each of them is attaching a data type to the character string "Abraham Lincoln". Most computer languages are only concerned with the data type in line 1. This is all they need to generate executable code. But logicians have been interested in more elaborate forms of data typing. Each of the statements mentions a valid data type in this logical sense. Logicians have noticed that data types corresponds to what they call "predicates" which are templates to form propositions that are either true or false. For example "is the name of a president of the USA" is a predicate. If you apply it to "Abraham Lincoln" you are stating the (true) proposition that "Abraham Lincoln" is the name of a president of the USA. And if you attach the same predicate to "Albert Einstein" you get a similar but false proposition.

When writing a program, programmers must first define their data. They don't just define the syntactic representation in terms of bits. They also define what the data will mean. A logician would say they define the logical data types, the predicates which are associated with the data. These predicates are documented in the specifications of the software, in comments included in the source code or in the names they give to the program variables. This knowledge is essential in understanding a program. However these predicates are not used for generating machine executable instructions. The predicates are not used by the computer for the manipulation of the symbols. During execution the predicates are implicit. They are defined by a convention the reader must know in order to be able to read the symbols correctly. They are for human understanding and verification that the program indeed does what it is intended to do.23 And they are also for the user of the program as he needs to understand the meanings of the inputs and outputs in order to use the program properly.

Data types in this extended logical sense relate to algorithms as follows. If you expect the data to be of some type, then the data is implicitly stating a proposition. You can tell which proposition by applying the predicate to the data. If you expect a quantity of hammers in your inventory and the data you get is 6, then you implicitly have a statement that you currently have 6 hammers in stock. All data is implicitly the statement of a proposition corresponding to its logical type.

When the algorithm process the data it implicitly carries out logical inferences on the corresponding propositions because a correctly working program must always produce data of the correct type. For example if you ask a program for the birth date of Theodore Roosevelt and the program returns October 27, 1858, it implicitly states that this is the birth date of Theodore Roosevelt because this is the proposition corresponding to the expected data type. The definition of correctness for a program is that it produces a logically correct answer. Programmers are well aware of this correspondence between predicates, data and correctness. They use it to design, understand and verify their programs.

There is a whole body of theory on how algorithms correspond to logic based on logical data types. The Curry-Howard correspondence is part of this theory. It works like a translation, similar to translating between Russian and Chinese, except that the translation is between two mathematical languages. If the algorithm is expressed in the language of λ-calculus then the Curry-Howard correspondence translates the algorithm into a proof of mathematical logic expressed in the language of predicate calculus. The translation works also in the other direction. Proofs of mathematical logic may likewise be translated into algorithms. In this sense an algorithm is really another expression for rules of logic. The difference is a matter of form and not substance.

As an alternative, when the algorithm is written in an imperative language instead of λ-calculus it may be assigned a logical semantics using Hoare logic. Poernomo, Crossley and Wirsing argue that Hoare logic is what the Curry-Howard correspondence becomes when it is adapted to imperative programs.24

To summarize the main points, algorithms are machine executable because their execution depends only on syntax with no need for a human to interpret their meaning. But they solve problems because the symbols have meanings.

5. All computations carried out by a stored program computer are mathematical computations carried out according to a universal mathematical algorithm.
Mathematicians have discovered that some algorithms have a universal property. They can compute all possible computable functions provided they are given some corresponding input called a program. Universal algorithms makes possible to build general purpose computers. When we have a machine able to compute a universal algorithm we can make it compute any function of our choosing by supplying it with the corresponding data. This is the difference between making a machine dedicated to carrying out a single algorithm and software.

When a general purpose computer built in this manner every program ends up being executed by the universal algorithm. Therefore every computation in is a mathematical computation according to a mathematical algorithm. This phenomenon is often referred to by the slogan "software is mathematics". This notion is often repeated on Groklaw.

Several universal algorithms are known. Here is a selection among the main ones.

There is SLD resolution which is used in the logic programming paradigm and languages such as Prolog. SLD resolution is a universal algorithm which applies rules of logic to the data.25

In functional programming various implementations of normal order β-reduction are used.26 These universal algorithms are used in languages derived from λ-calculus like LISP.

Instruction cycles are the preferred universal algorithms for imperative programming which is the most widely used programming paradigm. Instruction cycles have both hardware and software implementations. A hardware implementation results into the stored program computer architecture which is the dominant way of making general purpose programmable computers. Software implementations often take the form of virtual machines or bytecode interpreters.

The universal Turing machine plays an important role in the theoretical foundations of computer science. It played a role in the birth of computation theory. It has also been inspiration behind the invention of the stored program computer. Unlike the previously mentioned universal algorithm it is not used for actual computer programming.

When a universal algorithm is implemented in software the computer needs to be programmed twice. The first program uses the native instructions of the computer to implement the universal algorithm in software. The second program is the data given to the software universal algorithm.

The instruction cycle works as follows, assuming a hardware implementation in a stored program computer.27

  1. The CPU reads an instruction from main memory.
  2. The CPU decodes the bits of the instruction.
  3. The CPU executes the operation corresponding to the bits of the instruction.
  4. If required, the CPU writes the result of the instruction in main memory.
  5. The CPU finds out the location in main memory where the next instruction is located.
  6. The CPU goes back to step 1 for the next iteration of the cycle.

As you can see, the instruction cycle executes the instructions one after another in a sequential manner. In substance the instruction cycle is a recipe to "read the instructions and do as they say". This instruction themselves don't execute anything. They are data read and acted upon by the CPU.28

Not all universal algorithms use instructions as their input as the instruction cycle does. It is incorrect to assume every computer program is made of instructions because some programming languages target universal algorithms that don't use instructions as their input.

B. Some Errors of Facts Found in Arguments About Software and Patents

This section enumerates a few errors of facts that poison the discussion about software and patents. It is subdivided in several subsections, each of them is dedicated to one error. We explain what the error is and how it poisons legal arguments about abstract ideas and their applications. Each subsection is a standalone argument. Each of the errors is damaging and must be corrected.

The overarching argument for this section B is that these errors have a cumulative effect. Collectively they solidify the erroneous notion that the functions of software are performed solely through the physical properties of electrical circuits. Each error either disregard or deny the role of symbols and their meaning in computer programming. Then, the cumulative effect is that the expression of an abstract idea is conflated with the application of an idea. As a result, oftentimes patents on the expressions of abstract ideas are granted because they have been mistaken for the applications of these ideas.

1. The proper understanding of the term "mathematical algorithm" is the one given by mathematicians.

Historically the courts have had problem understanding the term "mathematical algorithm". For example the Federal Circuit stated in AT&T Corporation vs Excel Communications:

Courts have used the terms "mathematical algorithm," "mathematical formula," and "mathematical equation," to describe types of nonstatutory mathematical subject matter without explaining whether the terms are interchangeable or different. Even assuming the words connote the same concept, there is considerable question as to exactly what the concept encompasses.
Also see in re Warmerdam:

The difficulty is that there is no clear agreement as to what is a "mathematical algorithm", which makes rather dicey the determination of whether the claim as a whole is no more than that.

Part of the problem lies in the definitions they have used. Courts are not referring to the work of mathematicians when they try (and so far fail) to understand the meaning of this term.

In Gottschalk v. Benson the Supreme Court describes the term algorithm like this:

A procedure for solving a given type of mathematical problem is known as an "algorithm."
This is not an altogether wrong one-sentence summary, but it is too concise to be a complete definition. The details of the mathematically correct notion cannot be known if this sentence alone is used as the sole source of information.

In Typhoon Touch Technologies, Inc. v. Dell, Inc. the Federal Circuit explained their understanding:

The usage "algorithm" in computer systems has broad meaning, for it encompasses "in essence a series of instructions for the computer to follow," In re Waldbaum, 59 CCPA 940, 457 F.2d 997, 998 (1972), whether in mathematical formula, or a word description of the procedure to be implemented by a suitably programmed computer. The definition in Webster's New Collegiate Dictionary (1976) is quoted in In re Freeman, 573 F.2d 1237, 1245 (CCPA 1978): "a step-by-step procedure for solving a problem or accomplishing some end." In Freeman the court referred to "the term `algorithm' as a term of art in its broad sense, i.e., to identify a step-by-step procedure for accomplishing a given result." The court observed that "[t]he preferred definition of `algorithm' in the computer art is: `A fixed step-by-step procedure for accomplishing a given result; usually a simplified procedure for solving a complex problem, also a full statement of a finite number of steps.' C. Sippl & C. Sippl, Computer Dictionary and Handbook (1972)." Id. at 1246.
In particular the court in In re Freeman decided that these definitions of this term are more or less synonymous with process. Consequently the courts have tried to narrow down the understanding of mathematical algorithm to a subcategory of algorithms that the courts would deem "mathematical".

Because every process may be characterized as "a step-by-step procedure * * * for accomplishing some end," a refusal to recognize that Benson was concerned only with mathematical algorithms leads to the absurd view that the Court was reading the word "process" out of the statute.
This is where the problem occurs. The definitions the courts have used provide no insight into what makes an algorithm mathematical. As a result, the courts don't have the information they need to distinguish a mathematical algorithm from a process in the patent-law sense.

Mathematicians have told us what a mathematical algorithm is. The courts should use this definition. Then they would know what an algorithm is in the mathematical sense of the term.

A mathematical algorithm is a procedure for manipulating symbols which meet the additional requirements we have given above.29 We can ensure an algorithm is "mathematical" by verifying it meets the requirements of mathematics. It happens that the computations carried out by a computer always meet these requirements. The slogan "software is mathematics" is often used to refer to this conclusion. We may reach that conclusion in several ways. For the purposes of this response, it suffices to mention three of them.

First, we may just compare the manipulation of bits in a computer with the requirements of mathematics to see that there is a match. An algorithm is a procedure that solves problem through the mechanical execution of a manipulation of symbols. A programmer must find a way to solve the problem exclusively by syntactic means, without having the machine to refer to the semantic. This obligation is what ensures the algorithm always meet the requirements of mathematicians for an algorithm to be a mathematical algorithm.

The second way to reach this conclusion is to observe that software is always data given as input to a universal algorithm. Given that the universal algorithm is mathematical then the computation must be the execution of a mathematical algorithm

A third way to reach a similar conclusion is to use a programming language approach. We may ask whether the claimed method is implementable in the Concurrent ML extension of the programming language Standard ML. The official definition of the language specifies in mathematical terms which algorithm must be executed when a program is executed. Concurrent ML extends this specification to input/output routines and various concurrent programming constructs. A program written in this language is guaranteed to correspond to a mathematical algorithm given by the definition of the language.30

The patent eligibility of a computer implemented invention hinges on whether the claim is directed at an application of the mathematical algorithm as opposed to the algorithm itself. A logical conclusion of "software is mathematics" in the sense above is that any threshold test of whether a mathematical algorithm is present in the invention is always passed when software is used. Attempts to distinguish computer algorithms that are 'mathematical' from those which are not are contrary to the principles of computer science. Then the section 101 analysis must proceed to whether the claim is directed to a patent-eligible application of the algorithm as opposed to the patent-ineligible abstract idea. A proposal for doing this will be presented in section C below.

2. The vast majority of algorithms can carried out in practice for smaller inputs and are impractical for larger inputs.
Mathematicians know that algorithms must be executed in practice in order to actually solve problems. A procedure which can't be actually carried out won't solve anything. But still they have made a conscious decision to ignore the practical limitations of the computing agent in their criteria for accepting a procedure as an algorithm.31 This is in direct conflict with a frequently stated legal argument. Some people argue that whether or not the computation can be implemented in practice is one of the distinguishing factors between abstract mathematics and an application of mathematics.32 In one version of this argument it is argued that if the algorithm is hard to implement in practice then this is evidence that it is not an abstract idea.

The problem with this argument is that the burden of carrying out the steps on an algorithm increases with the quantity of data present in the input. There are few exceptions, but typical algorithms require at least to read their inputs. Then logically, if the size of the inputs increases, more work is required to read them. Then the input must be processed and again the amount of work increases with the quantity of data to be processed. All typical algorithms are practical to use for a small enough size of inputs. And all typical algorithms are impractical when the size of the data grows over a certain limit. Therefore all typical algorithms will both pass and fail the "can be implemented in practice" test depending on the size of the input.

In particular all ordinary arithmetic calculations may be either practical or impractical depending on how many decimals are required to write the numbers. Doubling the number pi with a precision of one trillion decimals is not something a human doing pencil and paper calculations can achieve in his lifetime. A computer can do it but there is no limit to infinity. If we increase the number of decimals to a high enough value the calculation is impractical on the fastest computers. This statement will remain true no matter how powerful our computer may be because their capacity will always be finite.

This is the point of the abstraction mathematicians have made. By ignoring the practical limitations they separate the mathematical properties of the algorithm from the capabilities of the computing agent. A test of whether the method may be carried out in practice is not testing for what a mathematical algorithm actually is.

We may compare algorithms with legal arguments. Courts enforce limits on the number of pages a brief may have and on the duration of oral arguments. Lawyers must find concise arguments that fall within these limits. This is not inventing a smaller stack of paper covered with ink or a faster process for emitting sounds in a courtroom. The argument remains an abstract idea even though concision makes it fit within physical limits.

Computations are mathematical written utterances because they are procedures for writing symbols. When a better algorithm is found the utterances are more concise. This is still a mathematical algorithm. The comparison with a legal argument is applicable because according to the Curry-Howard correspondence an algorithm is an expression of logic.33 An algorithm solves problems precisely because it uses sound principles of logic and arithmetic to derive the solution.

3. The printed matter doctrine should be applicable to computations.
What happens when the only new and nonobvious advances over the prior art are in the meaning of the symbols? For books and printing processes there is the printed matter doctrine. It is well understood that stories of hobbits traveling in faraway countries are not physical elements of books or printing processes. The contents of the book cannot be used to distinguish the invention over the prior art.

As far as Groklaw can tell there is no analogous doctrine about computations carried out by computers. This is a problem. There should be one.

Please take a pocket calculator. Now use it to compute 12+26. The result should be 38. Now give some non mathematical meanings to the numbers, say they are counts of apples. Use the calculator to compute 12 apples + 26 apples. The result should be 38 apples. Doe you see a difference in the calculator circuit? Here is the riddle. What kind of non mathematical meanings must be given to the numbers to make a patent eligible difference in the calculator circuit? Answer: it can't happen.

This example carries to programming. There is no difference in the computer structure between an instruction to add 12+26 and an instruction to add 12 apples + 26 apples. There is no difference in a computer structure between doing a calculation for the same of knowing the numerical answer and doing a calculation because the numbers mean something in the real world. If we use a computer to compute the trajectories of satellites in orbit the satellite and their trajectories are not computer parts. There are only instructions for manipulating numbers.

There are two issues there. First, if meaning doesn't make a difference in the computer structure then we can't argue a new specific machine is made on that basis alone. Second the difference between a pure mathematical calculation and and application of mathematics is the meaning given to numbers and other mathematical entities in the real world.

When the innovation lies strictly in the meaning with no physical difference in the machine then there is no patentable invention. At the very least the invention cannot be a machine or the operating process of a machine. We need a doctrine analogous to the printed matter doctrine to recognize these situations.

Here is another way to make the same point. Consider this claim.

A [computer / printing press] comprising a printing device and a microprocessor configured to use the printing device to print the story of hobbits traveling in faraway countries to destroy an evil anvil.

The words in brackets indicate a choice. This claim may be written indifferently to a computer or a printing press. A computer may be connected to a printed. A printing press may have an embedded microprocessor to control it. Logically the printed matter doctrine should apply in both scenarios. Even if we assume that destroying an anvil instead of a ring is a new and nonobvious improvement over Tolkien's The Lord of the Ring both claims should still be invalid.

We have an example of a claim where the printed matter doctrine should be applicable to a programmed computer. This raises the issue of where and how do we draw the line between claims where this doctrine applies and where it doesn't.

Technology does not provide a way to draw this line. For example we cannot distinguish between instructions and data. It is always possible to program a printing process with instructions which in effect mean "print the letter T, print the letter h, print the letter e, etc" until the whole book is printed. Or alternatively we can use a universal algorithm which does not rely on instructions as its input to transform any algorithm into non executable data. If the test relies on a technological difference then no matter how the courts may wish to define this test programmers will be able to arrange matters in such manner that their program falls on the side of the line they want. But if the test doesn't rely on technology, it is hard to see how can it be argued that a machine or its operating process has been patented.

We can make the argument for a computing version of the printed matter doctrine in a third manner. Let's compare the printing process with computing. Printing is a physical process which is performed through the physical properties of ink and paper. This process functions automatically without the intervention of a human mind. The specific book being printed is determined by data given as input to the printing press.

In a stored program computer, the computation is carried out by executing the instruction cycle. This instruction cycle is a physical process which is performed through the physical properties of an electrical circuit. This process functions automatically without the intervention of a human mind. The specific calculation is determined by data given as input to the instruction cycle.

There is no factual difference which would justify applying the printed matter doctrine to a printing process but not to the instruction cycle. The relationship between the meaning of symbols and the machine is exactly the same in both cases.

The Federal Circuit guidance given in in re Lowry is unhelpful:

The printed matter cases "dealt with claims defining as the invention certain novel arrangements of printed lines or characters, useful and intelligible only to the human mind." In re Bernhart, 417 F.2d 1395, 1399, 163 USPQ 611, 615 (CCPA 1969). The printed matter cases have no factual relevance where "the invention as defined by the claims requires that the information be processed not by the mind but by a machine, the computer." Id. (emphasis in original).

It is hard to see how this guidance can work. A claim on a configured printing press requires that the information be processed not by a human mind but by a machine, the printing press. The issue of meaning arise whether or not the human mind is an element of the process.

Software is much more likely to require the use of a human mind than a printing press. Many computer programs are interacting with their users, providing outputs and requiring inputs. In these circumstances part of the data processing is done by a human mind because human decisions are involved. On the other hand a printing press replicates the printed matter in an entirely automatic manner.

This is not the only flaw in Lowry. There isn't information useful and intelligible only to a human mind anymore. Authors write books using word processors. Books exist in electronic form and printing devices are controlled by computers. Printed characters are machine readable through optical character recognition (OCR) technology. The Perl programming language has been designed for the express purpose of processing text and it can process the result of an OCR scan.

The preceding paragraph assumes that "intelligible to a machine" means the ability to recognize the characters and process their syntax. If "intelligible" means the faculty to relate the syntax with meaning computers don't do that.34 This is precisely why programmers must use algorithms to solve problems.35

The Lowry test for the applicability of the printed matter doctrine is arbitrary and illogical. It is not consistent with technological reality.

4. The language used in the disclosure and claims in software patents rely on an inversion of the normal semantical relationships between symbols and their meaning.

The error discussed in this section occurs when this inversion of the normal semantical relationship is not acknowledged. This leads to a contradictory reading of Supreme Court precedents on section 101 subject matter patentability. But if the inversion is taken into account it is easy to see that Supreme Court precedents are consistent.

Let's use ink and paper as an analogy. The marks of ink represent letters and the letters form words which have meanings. So the normal semantical relationship goes from the physical substrate, the ink, to the symbol, the letter. And then it goes from the letters to the words, from the words to the sentences and ultimately to the meaning of the sentences.

This observation is applicable to the mathematical foundations of computing. Mathematics is a written language. The semantical relationships follow the normal progression, from ink to the symbols, from the symbols to the syntax of mathematical language and then to the mathematical entities like numbers which are denoted by the symbols. Then there is an additional relationship between math and whatever in the universe is described by means of math.

This applies to algorithms too. An algorithm is a mathematical procedure to solve problems, like the ordinary pencil and paper arithmetical calculations we have learned in school. When computing the computer write symbols that have the same semantical relationships. An algorithm is a procedure for writing and rewriting the symbols until we arrive at a solution of the problem.

We find in computers the same semantical progression except that the symbols are not written on paper. Computers use electrical, magnetic and optical phenomenons to represent bits. The bits are symbols representing boolean values and numbers. Finally the numbers means whatever in the universe is described by the numbers. The computations are manipulations of the bits according to some algorithm. This is part of mathematical foundations of computer science.

Sometimes we may invert this semantical relationship. For example we may enter a bookstore and ask for the book where hobbits travel in faraway countries where live elves and orcs to destroy an evil ring. Then the store keeper will bring a copy of Tolkien's Lord of the Ring. This is describing the physical book by referring to its contents. Instead of using the book to tell the novel we use (an outline of) the novel to refer to the book.

This inversion of the semantical relationship occurs in software patents. The functions of the software are disclosed and claimed. This language is written in terms of the meaning of the data. If the patent is on a payroll system the functions of the software will be described in terms of employees, wages and deductions for example. The expectation is that a skilled programmer will be able to write the software from this disclosure. Also, the claim is presumed to describe a new machine which is a programmed computer. The claimed invention is either this machine or some machine process such as transistors turning on and off while carrying out the functions of the software. This is describing the physical device in terms of its meaning, exactly like the physical book may be described by an outline of the novel.

This point is related to the distinction between the expression of an abstract idea and an application of an idea. A mathematical idea is written using symbols. This is an expression of the idea in a sense close to copyright law. But mathematics may be used to describe something else, like a rocket in flight or the finances of a corporation. This is the application of mathematics. We can see these concepts are related to mathematical language. In semiotics terms, the expression of the idea is a sign-vehicle and the application is a referent.

A mathematical calculation involving pure numbers like 12+36=48 is not distinguishable from an applied calculation like 12 apples + 36 apples = 48 apples unless we consider the meaning of the numbers. In this example, the meaning is counts of apples. Therefore the difference between pure abstract mathematics and applied mathematics is in the meaning.

The same mathematical expression may or may not have a meaning outside of mathematics depending on context. It can be both pure mathematics or applied mathematics depending on what is the meaning. The same is true of algorithms. The same algorithm can be used for both pure mathematics and applied mathematics depending on the intent of its user. This supports the notion that an expression of a mathematical idea is a sign-vehicle and its application is a referent.

We may represent the inversion of semantical relationships in a picture:

This inversion is not a problem as long as everyone understand and acknowledge this is what is going on. The translation between the two views is straightforward and everybody will understand each other.

Problems occur when people are oblivious to the normal semantical relationships and only consider the legal view. Then they argue the computer is described by mathematics in a manner analogous to a description of the physical universe according to the laws of physics. Then they will treat the programmed computer as an application instead of an expression of mathematics. This conflation is indicated in the diagram above.

This argument is found explicitly in in re Bernhart:

[A]ll machines function according to laws of physics which can be mathematically set forth if known. We cannot deny patents on machines merely because their novelty may be explained in terms of such laws if we are to obey the mandate of Congress that a machine is subject matter for a patent.
A device described according to the laws of physics is the meaning of the mathematical language. It is not the language itself. But the computation as carried out by the computer is the actual manipulation of symbols representing numbers. They are the digital counterpart of pencil and paper calculations. This is illustrated in the picture below.

This picture shows the laws of physics follows the normal semantical relationships: from symbols to math and from math to the described device. But a patent goes the other way round because the programmed computer is where the symbols are stored and manipulated. The Bernhart law of physics argument is valid when applied to a device described according to the laws of physics. But when its is applied to a software patent claim this difference must be taken into account and the argument should not apply.

Let's use a payroll system as an example. The algorithm is described in terms of calculations about hours worked, hourly rates and deductions. None of that is machine parts. A payroll algorithm is not a mathematical description of the computer. It is a description of the calculations which are applicable to payrolls. We can use this as a description of the programmed computer only when we invert the semantical relationship and use the functions of the software as a description of what the computer must do with the bits. This is not like the laws of physics.

If we take the laws of physics argument seriously there is no arithmetic calculation which is abstract mathematics. The logic goes like this. All mathematical formulas may be used as a mathematical description of a programmed computer for doing the corresponding calculations. To paraphrase the court in Berhhart, we cannot deny patents on machines merely because their novelty may be explained in terms of such formulas if we are to obey the mandate of Congress that a machine is subject matter for a patent.

When we disregard the inversion of the semantical relationship an application of mathematics is incorrectly conflated with a written expression in the language of mathematics. Or in the terms of of semiotics, the sign-vehicle is conflated with the referent. This leads to a contradictory reading to the Supreme Court precedents in Gottschalk v. Benson, Parker v. Flook and Diamond v. Diehr. The factual difference between Diehr and the other two cases is that in Diehr the referent is claimed but it is not claimed in the other two cases. The only basis we have to find that there is an application of mathematics in Diehr but not in Benson and Flook is that the referent is claimed. This is consistent with the view that an application of mathematics is a referent while an expression of a mathematical idea is a sign-vehicle. But if we don't distinguish the expression from the application we cannot distinguish Benson and Flook from Diehr and the three cases are contradictory.

A contradictory reading of these cases cannot be correct. Therefore the proper interpretation of these cases should be that an application of a mathematical algorithm is a referent and not a sign-vehicle. This is also the conclusion which is reached when the proper semantical relationships are taken into consideration when we analyze how algorithms perform their functions.

5. In a stored program computer the functions of software are performed through a combination of defining the meaning of data and giving input to an already implemented algorithm.
The error in this section is a common misunderstanding of the operating principles of a computer. The courts have ruled that programming a computer is the act configuring a general purpose of computer into a specific machine for performing the functions of the software. This is the legal doctrine that programming a computer makes a machine different from the unprogrammed computer. This view is technically incorrect because the functions of software are not implemented in this manner. The consequence of this error is that patents are granted on machines when no machine has been invented.

There are two main arguments supporting this doctrine: the new function argument and the change to the machine structure argument.

According to the new function argument the configured circuit can perform a function the circuit without the configuration is not capable of performing. Therefore the configured circuit is a different circuit from the one without the configuration.

The change to the machine structure argument has been stated in In re Bernhart : "[I]f a machine is programmed in a certain new and unobvious way, it is physically different from the machine without that program; its memory elements are differently arranged."36

These two arguments follows from a naive and technically incorrect understanding of computer programming. In this understanding the functions of software are implemented by storing the instructions of the program in main memory. Then, according to this understanding, the structure of the general purpose computer is changed and it becomes a specific machine able to perform the functions of software. This view is incorrect because the functions of software are not related to the machine structure in this manner.

Some old general purpose computers like the ancient ENIAC were programmed by physically rewiring the computer using a plug board. This kind of programming makes a particular circuit for each program. This is an obsolete design. Most modern general purpose computers are build according to the stored program computer architecture. They are not programmed with plug boards or equivalent devices. These computers are programmed through a combination of two techniques: (a) defining the meaning of data, and, (b) giving some input to an already implemented algorithm. These two techniques, taken alone or in combination, do not configure the computer to make a specific machine. They leave the structure of the machine unchanged.

The naive understanding of programing departs from the technically correct view in three ways.

  1. The naive understanding of computer programming ignores the role of the meaning of data.
  2. Main memory is a moving part of a computer. A physical change to a moving part of a machine doesn't make a structurally different machine. It is the action of the process by which the machine operates.
  3. The mere act of storing data in memory does not implement functionality. This only happens when the data is given as input to an algorithm. This remains true when the data is instructions for a program.
  4. All data may be used to implement functionality when given as input to an algorithm. This capability is not limited to instructions.

We illustrate these issues using a multiplication algorithm as an example. We assume the algorithm is implemented as a dedicated digital circuit for the sake of making clear what is the relationship between functionality and the underlying hardware. Then the explanation will also apply to the hypothetical specific machine which is created when a computer is programmed.

Our hypothetical circuit performs a series of multiplications. It takes as input a series of number, like 2, 5, 7, 12, 43, and multiply them by the same predefined number. The circuit is configured by recording this predefined number in a hardware register.37 If the number in the register is 2 then the circuit will double the sample series above to produce the result 4, 10, 14, 24, 86.

Let's call this circuit a multiplying circuit. Then we may write a series of claims:

  1. A multiplying circuit comprising an arithmetic unit and a register configured to double a plurality of numbers.
  2. A multiplying circuit comprising an arithmetic unit and a register configured to triple a plurality of numbers.
  3. The multiplying circuit of claim 1 where the numbers are counts of apples.
  4. The multiplying circuit of claim 2 where the numbers are counts of oranges.
  5. A multiplying circuit comprising an arithmetic unit and a register configured to quadruple a plurality of counts of peppercorns.

The claims are directed to a hardware implementation of the algorithm. However the details of the hardware are purposefully left out of the claims. As they are written they may as well read on the specific machine that results, according to patent law, from the programming of a general purpose computer. This ambiguity is intended for educational purposes. It builds an easy to understand correspondence between the operation of the hardware and the action of the algorithm. Any argument about the hardware circuit obviously transposes to the equivalent software implementation.

Claims 1 and 2 illustrate the meaning of the phrase "configured to" when it is applied to a circuit for executing an algorithm. In claim 1 the function is doubling. In claim 2 the function is tripling.38 These functions are implemented by storing a number in the circuit register. For claim 1 this number is 2. The number is 3 for claim 2. Configuring circuits for performing some functions is the act of storing one or more numbers in a memory element. In the case of the multiplying circuit only one number is needed and the memory element is a register. In the case of a stored program computer we store long series of numbers in the computer main memory. Often the numbers represent instructions to be executed by the instruction cycle but this is not always the case. Often other numbers are used as inputs to other algorithms. For example this would occur in a software implementation of claims 1 and 2.

The naive understanding of computer programming ignores the role of the meaning of data.

Claims 3 and 4 show how the meaning of data relates to functionality. Claim 3 doubles counts of apples instead of doubling plain numbers as in claim 1. And claim 4 triples counts of oranges instead of tripling counts of plain numbers as in claim 2. The difference is strictly in the meaning of numbers. The physical configuration of the machine is unchanged when compared to claims 1 and 2. This method of implementing functionality is a pure operation of meaning.

There is no way to argue that defining the meaning of data makes a circuit different from the circuit without the meaning. We cannot argue there is a change to the machine structure because no change at all is made to the machine. Then arguing the circuit must be different because it performs a new function is nonsensical.39

This point alone suffices to refute the doctrine that programing a computer makes a different machine. The reason is that the meaning of numbers is not a machine part. The sole operation of giving some non-mathematical meaning to numbers can never make a machine different from the one where the numbers don't have this meaning.

In claim 5 the two programming techniques are used in combination. A number is configured in the register as input to the multiplying algorithm and simultaneously we define the numbers to be counts of peppercorns. Programs for general purpose computers use this same combination of techniques. The meaning of data is defined and numbers are stored in main memory and given as input to algorithms.

The contribution of the count of peppercorns to the circuit structure is nil. This is defining the meaning of the numbers like in claims 3 and 4. This claim doesn't recite a circuit different from a circuit configured to quadruple plain numbers. This same point is applicable to a stored program computer. Reciting the meaning of the data does not direct a claim to a computer different from one that manipulates plain numbers because meaning is not a machine part.

If someone were to insist on salvaging the doctrine from this argument, he may try to remove the meaning of data from the definition of the functionality and claim a specific machine for performing whatever remains of the function. This attempt would fail for two reasons. First for all practical purposes it would eviscerate the doctrine. Software is useless unless the data has meaning and utility is a requirement for patentability. Second once the meaning is removed the resulting function is a manipulation of plain numbers. Then the claim should be invalid because the mathematical algorithm exception applies.

A patentable application of mathematics must actually use the referent. Merely referring to it is not sufficient because, then, there is no contribution of the referent to the invention structure when compared to an identical manipulation of pure numbers.

Main memory is a moving part of a computer. A physical change to a moving part of a machine doesn't make a structurally different machine. It is the action of the process by which the machine operates.

The issue may arise of whether the changes to the memory elements resulting from programming the computer suffice to make machine different from the unprogrammed computer. The answer is that no such machine is made because memory elements are moving part of the circuit. They can be changed billions of times per second.40 Clearly a different machine isn't made every time one of these changes occur. To rule otherwise yields the absurd result that no machine can perform a computation until the end because it always become a different machine every time a memory element is altered.

Storing information in memory never makes a structural change to the computer. This action is always part of the execution of the electrical process by which the computer operates.41 Regardless of how a computer is programmed this electrical process is always the execution of the instruction cycle.

The mere act of storing data in memory does not implement functionality. This only happens when the data is given as input to an algorithm. This remains true when the data is instructions for a program.

If someone were to insist that programming a computer makes a different machine from the unprogrammed computer he has to argue that he can somehow distinguish some memory changes that make a different machine from other changes that don't.42 This argument is not defensible because the technology doesn't work in this manner.

Looking at claims 1 and 2 again, there is no physical difference between a number which is used to configure a multiplying circuit and a number which is used for another purpose. The bits representing the number are identical in both cases. The difference is in what is done with the number after it has been stored. If we transpose this logic to a stored program computer, there is no physical difference between numbers in memory which are instructions to the microprocessor and numbers which are used for another purpose. Again the bits representing numbers are identical. The difference is in what is done with the numbers afterwards.

There are programs which use instructions as ordinary numeric data without executing them. Examples are programs which compute checksums or hash functions to verify that the file containing the instructions has not been tampered with. When instructions are stored in memory for this purpose the functionality is not imparted to the computer. The instructions will result into functionality only when they are given as input to the instruction cycle.

The changes in the memory elements do not impart functionality to a computer. The act of giving the data as input to an already implemented algorithm imparts the functionality. This is why we can't distinguish memory changes that makes a structurally different machine from those that don't. The difference is in how the data is used and not in which data is used or what happens to the memory.

All data may be used to implement functionality when given as input to an algorithm. This capability is not limited to instructions.

The naive view of computers asserts that because the instructions have a special meaning to the hardware they impart functionality while other data without such special meaning will not. This is not how its works. Instructions are series of numbers given as input to an algorithm implemented in hardware which is the instruction cycle.43 But this is only one of the several algorithms programmers may use for this purpose.44 Programmers can and do implement functionality with data which is not instructions recognizable by the hardware.

As a general rule every algorithm that accepts multiple arguments can be used to produce more functions by partially specifying one of its argument in the manner illustrated by claims 1 and 2. Any type of data can be used as an input as long as the chosen algorithm can process it.

The range of functions which can be so specified will vary depending on the capabilities of the algorithm. Some algorithms are especially prone to be used in this manner. The extreme case is the various universal algorithms mentioned in section A.5 supra. Each of these algorithms can compute all functions which are computable. But non-universal algorithms can also be used, although they are more limited in the range of what they can compute. For example algorithms for pattern matching using regular expressions can be used for a wide range of text processing functions. And algorithms for reading and writing data in a database can be used for a wide range of storage and retrieval functions. Please note how some of these algorithms accept as input data which is not instructions to the hardware.

Conclusion

The main memory of the computer is always a moving part of the device regardless of which type of information is stored and how it is used afterwards.45 Changing the contents of main memory never makes a structurally different machine. In addition defining the meaning of data makes no changes whatsoever to the computer. The doctrine that programming a computer makes a machine different from the unprogrammmed computer corresponds to a naive and incorrect view of how functionality relates to the underlying hardware. The effect of this doctrine is to incorrectly extend the patentability of machines to claims where the actual invention is clearly not a machine.

6. The meaning of data distinguishes an algorithm from an application of the physical properties of a machine.

The Court of Customs and Patents Appeals once said: ( In re Noll )

There is nothing abstract about the claimed invention. It comprises physical structure, including storage devices and electrical components uniquely configured to perform specified functions through the physical properties of electrical circuits to achieve controlled results.

The functions of software are not always performed through the physical properties of electrical circuit. Software relies on the meaning of data and this is not a machine part. And most importantly, when data has no meaning, an algorithm doesn't solve its problem.

It is possible to view the computer as a machine that functions according to the laws of physics. It may be argued that the computer will functions without a human mind watching the meaning of the bits inside the computers. The same may be said of a printing press. In most software patents what is claimed is not the sole operation of the machine according to the laws of physics. Semantical elements are claimed. They are needed to infringe. This distinguishes the invention from a claim on a machine operating according to the laws of physics.

In sections B1 through B.5, five independent errors of fact have been identified. All five errors can be argued separately and they should all be corrected.

To make matters worse the role of meaning is not acknowledged. This sixth error seems to be a recurring theme underlying several of the previous five errors. This is a major problem because meaning is the very thing that makes computers useful. As a result, the subject matter of the invention is often mistaken for something physical when nothing physical has actually been invented.

The effect of the errors is cumulative. They prevent the patent system from understanding the difference between an abstract mathematical idea and the application of this idea.

C. What Is an Abstract Idea in Software and How Expressions of Ideas Differ From Applications of Ideas.

This section argues that semiotics is the proper approach to define what is an abstract idea in computer programming. Some alternative approaches are examined and rejected. This section also includes an examination of why mathematical subject matter is abstract and why the semiotics approach will correctly identify this type of abstract ideas.

1. Mathematical algorithms are abstract ideas.

It is understood in case law that mathematical algorithms are a subcategory of abstract ideas. We explain in this section how the principles of mathematics justify this view.

An algorithm is often abstract because it is designed to handle a potentially infinite range of inputs. This is the case of all arithmetic operations because there is no limit to how many digits a number may have. This is also the case of many nonnumerical algorithms such as searching text which are designed to work on arbitrarily large text. Planet Earth is not vast enough to make concrete implementations of "infinite". Data of arbitrarily large size are abstractions.

An algorithm is abstract because it is a procedure defined in terms that ignores the limitations of time and space of its practical implementation. It is designed to produce the correct answer for all size of inputs whether or not the resources to handle this input are available.46

An algorithm is a procedure for manipulating symbols. We note that a symbols is an abstract entity is different from a mark of ink on paper or an electric charge in a capacitor.47 The same algorithm may be implemented with a diversity of technologies where the same symbol has different physical representations. The algorithm is abstract because it is a manipulation of the abstract symbol. It is not a physical process for manipulating the physical representations.

An algorithm is abstract because its utility depends on meaning. The meaning of symbols is not a machine part. It is not a physical element of the machine.

Algorithms are analogous to novels, legal briefs and other forms of text. They have to be represented physically and yet they are abstract. Software patents often contain claims directed to the physical representations as long they convey the recited meaning. These claims are charades. They are attempts to preempt the underlying abstract ideas by claiming the physical means that are used to express them on the basis of their meanings.

2. Semiotics is the proper approach to define what is an abstract idea in software.

The question arises of how do we distinguish a claim on an abstract idea such as a mathematical calculation from a claim on an application of the idea. We argue that the proper way to answer this question is to use the concepts and vocabulary of semiotics,48 as in the picture below.

We rely on the notion that mathematics is a language and a computation is a written expression on this language. The symbols must be written somehow, often with pencil and paper, but also by electronic meas in a computer. The computation itself is a manipulation of symbols in this language. The symbols represent various mathematical entities like numbers and boolean values. If mathematics is used for a practical application these abstract mathematical entities model something in the physical reality.

In semiotics term the computer is a sign-vehicle, a physical device used to represent the sign. Whatever physical reality is referred to by the data is a referent. In-between the abstract mathematical ideas are interpretants. They are thoughts in the mind of the programmer, or in the mind of the user of the computer.

There is room to argue whether a number is an interpretant, a thought in the mind of humans, or an abstract referent, something that exists in a parallel abstract universe. This is a controversial topic in the philosophy of mathematics. A similar question may be raised with such concepts as commodity hedging. The law shouldn't be concerned with this debate. Either way the mathematical entities are abstract and not patentable. It should be acceptable to assimilate abstract referents with interpretants for legal purposes.

The Supreme Court in Diamond v, Diehr said: (footnote omitted, bold added)

We recognize, of course, that when a claim recites a mathematical formula (or scientific principle or phenomenon of nature), an inquiry must be made into whether the claim is seeking patent protection for that formula in the abstract. A mathematical formula as such is not accorded the protection of our patent laws, Gottschalk v. Benson, 409 U. S. 63 (1972), and this principle cannot be circumvented by attempting to limit the use of the formula to a particular technological environment. Parker v. Flook, 437 U. S. 584 (1978). Similarly, insignificant postsolution activity will not transform an unpatentable principle into a patentable process. Ibid. To hold otherwise would allow a competent draftsman to evade the recognized limitations on the type of subject matter eligible for patent protection. On the other hand, when a claim containing a mathematical formula implements or applies that formula in a structure or process which, when considered as a whole, is performing a function which the patent laws were designed to protect (e. g., transforming or reducing an article to a different state or thing), then the claim satisfies the requirements of § 101.

Please refer to the part in bold. We argue that this kind of structure or process must be a referent. It cannot be a sign-vehicle such as a programmed computer because it is a representation of the mathematical language itself. A sign-vehicle is not an application of the language. To hold otherwise would allow to claim mathematical subject matter because an expression in the language must always have some form of physical structure. Whenever the claim is directed to a sign-vehicle an inquiry must be made into whether the only nonobvious advances over the prior art are interpretants. If this is the case the claim is directed to the abstract meaning of the mathematical language.

3. This description of abstract ideas is technology neutral and it doesn't require to determine whether the algorithm is 'mathematical'.

Mathematics is mentioned in this discussion in part because algorithms are the only type of procedures computers are capable of executing49 and in part because a mathematical algorithm exception has been created by Supreme Court precedents. But the semiotics approach is applicable to all manipulations of symbols whether or not they are mathematical. Therefore, if this approach is adopted, the issue of whether or not a mathematical algorithm is involved can be eschewed.

This semiotics approach is not limited to software. It is applicable in all circumstances where a sign is involved. It doesn't matter if the sign is a stored program computer or some other technology like a dedicated circuit. The issue of meaning is handled in the same manner.

These circumstances are advantageous. There is no need to design some special test on what is 'mathematical' or what is 'software'. Also the notions of semiotics are not that hard to understand and they require no deep knowledge of mathematics or computer science. This leads to a test for abstract ideas which is workable for judges and juries with little or no mathematical and technology background. This test is also consistent with the established printed matter case law.50 It helps draw a logical boundary between copyright and patent law because it distinguishes the expression of an idea from the application of the idea.

4. There is no alternative to this description of abstract ideas.

Previous attempts to test for "abstract ideas" in software have failed. All these attempts have disregarded the issue of meaning. No test will succeed until the role of meaning is taken into consideration. The problem is that every expression of an idea must have a physical representation. Then it is easy to give a claim preempting an abstract idea a façade of concreteness by directing it to a sign-vehicle defined by its meaning. It is impossible to analyze the subject matter of this type of claims unless it is recognized that they are sign-vehicles and they have meanings.

Abstract is not synonymous with "vague or overly broad". Mathematical subject matter such as algorithms is abstract but it is narrowly and precisely defined.51

Abstract is not the opposite of "useful". The contents of a reference manual or a dictionary is useful but it is an interpretant which is an abstract idea. Also the ordinary pencil and paper procedures for arithmetic calculations are abstract mathematical algorithms and they have practical uses in accounting, engineering and many other disciplines.

Tests based on whether the invention is practically difficult to implement don't work because most mathematical algorithms are practical to implement when the size of the input is small enough and practically impossible to implement when the size of the input is large enough.52

The Federal Circuit has tried for years to find a definition of what makes an idea abstract. They report that they have failed.

From MySpace, Inc. v. GraphOn Corp.:

When it comes to explaining what is to be understood by "abstract ideas" in terms that are something less than abstract, courts have been less successful. The effort has become particularly problematic in recent times when applied to that class of claimed inventions loosely described as business method patents. If indeterminacy of the law governing patents was a problem in the past, it surely is becoming an even greater problem now, as the current cases attest.

In an attempt to explain what an abstract idea is (or is not) we tried the "machine or transformation" formula--the Supreme Court was not impressed. Bilski, 130 S.Ct. at 3226-27. We have since acknowledged that the concept lacks of a concrete definition: "this court also will not presume to define `abstract' beyond the recognition that this disqualifying characteristic should exhibit itself so manifestly as to override the broad statutory categories of eligible subject matter… ." Research Corp. Techs., Inc. v. Microsoft Corp., 627 F.3d 859, 868 (Fed.Cir.2010).

Our opinions spend page after page revisiting our cases and those of the Supreme Court, and still we continue to disagree vigorously over what is or is not patentable subject matter. See, e.g., Dealertrack, Inc. v. Huber, ___ F.3d ___ (Fed. Cir.2012) (Plager, J., dissenting-in-part); Classen Immunotherapies, Inc. v. Biogen IDEC, 659 F.3d 1057 (Fed.Cir.2011) (Moore, J., dissenting); Ass'n for Molecular Pathology, 653 F.3d 1329 (Fed.Cir. 2011) (concurring opinion by Moore, J., dissenting opinion by Bryson, J.); see also In re Ferguson, 558 F.3d 1359 (Fed.Cir. 2009) (Newman, J., concurring).

This effort to descriptively cabin § 101 jurisprudence is reminiscent of the oenologists trying to describe a new wine. They have an abundance of adjectives--earthy, fruity, grassy, nutty, tart, woody, to name just a few--but picking and choosing in a given circumstance which ones apply and in what combination depends less on the assumed content of the words than on the taste of the tongue pronouncing them.

From CLS Bank International v. Alice Corporation PTY. LTD.:

The abstractness of the "abstract ideas" test to patent eligibility has become a serious problem, leading to great uncertainty and to the devaluing of inventions of practical utility and economic potential. See Donald S. Chisum, Weeds and Seeds in the Supreme Court's Business Method Patent Decision: New Directions for Regulating Patent Scope, 15 Lewis & Clark L. Rev. 11, 14 (2011) ("Because of the vagueness of the concepts of an `idea' and `abstract,'… the Section 101 abstract idea preemption inquiry can lead to subjectively-derived, arbitrary and unpredictable results. This uncertainty does substantial harm to the effective operation of the patent system."). In Bilski, the Supreme Court offered some guidance by observing that "[a] principle, in the abstract, is a fundamental truth; an original cause; a motive; these cannot be patented, as no one can claim in either of them an exclusive right." Bilski II, 130 S. Ct. at 3230 (quoting Le Roy v. Tatham, 55 U.S. (14 How.) 156, 175 (1852). This court has also attempted to define "abstract ideas," explaining that "abstract ideas constitute disembodied concepts or truths which are not `useful' from a practical standpoint standing alone, i.e., they are not `useful' until reduced to some practical application." Alappat, 33 F.3d at 1542 n.18 (Fed. Cir. 1994). More recently, this court explained that the "disqualifying characteristic" of abstractness must exhibit itself "manifestly" "to override the broad statutory categories of patent eligible subject matter." Research Corp., 627 F.3d at 868. Notwithstanding these well-intentioned efforts and the great volume of pages in the Federal Reporters treating the abstract ideas exception, the dividing line between inventions that are directed to patent ineligible abstract ideas and those that are not remains elusive. "Put simply, the problem is that no one understands what makes an idea `abstract.'" Mark A. Lemley et al., Life After Bilski, 63 Stan. L. Rev. 1315, 1316 (2011).

In section B supra we have identified that the source of these problems is the refusal to acknowledge the role of symbols and their meaning in computer programming. There is a failure to consider what is a algorithm in mathematics.53 Had this notion been considered the role of symbols and meaning would have been apparent. Then there is a failure to recognize the similarities between the computer instruction cycle and a printing process.54 This recognition too would have made apparent the role of symbols and their meaning. There is also the failure to acknowledge that the language of a typical software patent inverts the normal semantical relationships between a sign-vehicle and the referent. This failure yields an inconsistent reading of the Supreme Court precedents of Benson, Flook and Diehr.55 It also leads to the incorrect conclusion that the functions of software are performed exclusively through the physical properties of electrical circuits.56 This conclusion is cemented by the doctrine that programming a computer makes a machine structurally different from the unprogrammed computer.

The cure is to acknowledge the linguistic aspects of mathematics and take into account that a computer is a sign-vehicle. It is a device for manipulating bits and bits are symbols with meanings. Then the proper definition of abstract ideas becomes apparent.

D. The Effect on Innovation of Patent Rights Granted on the Expressions of Abstract Ideas.

Software patents don't promote innovation because they can't. The burden imposed on job creating software authors is large. They cannot possibly clear all rights to their own products. The consequences are deleterious. Not only software authors can't be secure in their own property but they can't use the disclosure from patents by fear of being liable for treble damages. In addition, the normal costs/benefits analysis of patents is not applicable to software development. None of the factors that normally allow patents to promote innovation function according to theory in the computer programming art. Therefore there is no reason to believe software patents promote innovation.

1. Clearing all patents rights on expression of ideas is overly burdensome.
Let's imagine a regime where proprietary rights may be granted to each particular idea. In this imaginary regime the author of a book, any book, would be required to secure the rights to each idea he is using. Each sentence expresses an idea which may be owned by someone. Each combination of sentences makes a more complex idea. The author is expected to check each of these ideas, determine whether it is in the public domain or if it is owned by someone, and in the latter case secure the rights to the idea or remove it from his work.

It is not realistic to expect authors to comply with this requirement because it is overly burdensome. The rights cannot be cleared because the number of ideas in a book is just to great to check them all. Authors would have to choose between to quit writing or risk being sued. This regime would hinder the creation of new works of authorship because it would put all the authors who choose to keep writing at a perpetual risk of infringement.

This is exactly the kind of regime patent law imposes on computer programmers. Case law doesn't recognize that a computation is the expression of an idea, exactly like English sentences in a book. This is wrong. Programs are useful because data has meaning. They solve problems because the computation implements operations of logic through a syntactic manipulation of symbols.57

Software is written in the form of lines of code. The source code is a copyrightable expression and it is not patented. But source code corresponds to a computation. Because the computation is a manipulation of symbols it is also an expression of an idea. Patents rights are granted to this expression and this is where the problem lies.

Each line of code is roughly similar to a sentence in English in that each of them expresses an idea. Like sentences, lines of code are grouped to make more complex ideas. But under the current case law every single one of these ideas is specifying a physical process which is performed through the physical properties of an electrical circuit. Each of these processes may be the subject matter of a patent. Typical software has between thousands and millions of lines of code. The number of ideas which may potentially infringe on someone's patent is enormous.

Mark Lemley quantifies the numbers of patents which may be applicable to a software product.58

Because computer products tend to involve complex, multi-component technology, any given product is potentially subject to a large number of patents. A few examples: 3G wireless technology was subject to more than 7000 claimed "essential" patents as of 2004; the number is doubtless much higher now.72 WiFi is subject to hundreds and probably thousands of claimed essential patents.73 And the problem is even worse than these numbers suggest, since both 3G wireless technology and WiFi are not themselves products but merely components that must be integrated into a final product. Some industry experts have estimated that 250,000 patents go into a modern smartphone.74 Even nominally open-source technologies may turn out to be subject to hundreds or thousands of patents.75 The result is what Carl Shapiro has called a "patent thicket"-- a complex of overlapping patent rights that simply involves too many rights to cut through.76

----

______________

[Footnotes]

[72] For discussion and sources, see Mark A. Lemley & Carl Shapiro, Patent Holdup and Royalty Stacking, 85 Tex. L. Rev. 1991 (2007). Information on patents essential to 3G wireless technology is collected at http://www.3gpp2.org/, though that includes only patent disclosed to that group.

[73] Ed Sutherland, WiMax, 802.11n Renew Patent Debate (Apr. 7, 2005), http://www.wifiplanet.com/columns/article.php/3495951.

[74] See http://googleblog.blogspot.com/2011/08/when-patents-attack-android.html (statement of David Drummond, Chief Legal Officer at Google).

[75] Id. (discussing patents that threaten the open-source Android operating system). Microsoft, Nokia, Apple and others have all filed suit against makers of Android phones, part of a crazy tangle of litigation. See http://www.flickr.com/photos/ floorsixtyfour/5061246255/.

[76] Carl Shapiro, Navigating the Patent Thicket: Cross Licenses, Patent Pools, and Standard-Setting, in 1 Innovation Policy and the Economy 119 (Adam Jaffe et al. eds., 2000). See also Michael Heller & Rebecca S. Eisenberg, Can Patents Deter Innovation? The Anticommons in Biomedical Research, 280 Sci. 698 (1998).

Christina Mulligan and Timothy B. Lee have observed59 the burden of compliance with patents depends primarily on two numbers: the number of patents which may be potentially infringed and the numbers of firms which write software. Both numbers are large. Over 40,000 software patents are granted every year in the US. Also every firm having an internal IT department develops software. It is common even for small enterprises to own a web site. Each of these firm may potentially infringing on some software patent and in an ideal world each of them must check all applicable patents for possible infringement. The size of the task is staggering:60

Even if a patent lawyer only needed to look at a patent for 10 minutes, on average, to determine whether any part of a particular firm's software infringed it, it would require roughly 2 million patent attorneys, working full-time, to compare every firm's products with every patent issued in a given year.

This calculation covers just the work of keeping up with the newly issued patents every year. Checking already issued patents is not included.

This result is justified by simple arithmetic. The assumptions are 40,000 patents issued per year, 600,000 firms that actively write software, and each attorney is capable of working approximately 2000 billable hours per year. Then the math is straightforward: 40,000 patents*600,000 firms*(10 minutes per patent-firm pair)/(2000*60 minutes per attorney)=2 million attorneys.

These assumptions are admittedly speculative. It doesn't matter. There are only roughly 40,000 registered patent attorneys and patent agents in the US. Even if we alter the assumptions by a large margin the patent bar clearly doesn't have enough members to perform the task.

Even if we consider only the work required within a single organization, this is still an overly burdensome task. Mulligan and Lee examine a simple hypothetical scenario where 30,000 firms making widgets own one patent each for a total of 30,000 patents. Then they inquire how mush work it is for each participant to evaluate whether they infringe on the remaining 29,999 patents.61

Each of the 30,000 firms would need to hire a patent attorney to examine 29,999 other patents, which takes 1 hour per patent, so attorneys would spend a total of 30,000 * 29,999 * 1 hour = 899,970,000 hours. Assuming a typical attorney bills 2000 hours of work per year, each firm would need just shy of 15 attorneys to examine 29,999 patents.
This analysis assumes each firm want to complete the work in exactly a year. It also assumes that lawyers can determine whether a given patent is infringed. This is not always the case. It is notorious that this kind of analysis is not dependable.62

The analysis also assumes software firms can wait until the analysis is done before releasing their products in the marketplace. This is usually not the case. There is a strong first mover advantage in the software industry. Delays may jeopardize the commercial success of the product. Releasing the software before the patent search is completed may lead to a finding of willful infringement and treble damages. A company may be better off not to search for patents at all than release a product before the search is completed.

Also, patent compliance is not a one-time event. Software is constantly being modified. Products are constantly being upgraded. It is commonplace to release so-called "beta-tests", that is unfinished versions of the product for the purpose of testing. After one or more such testing releases an official version is produced. Then various bug fixes are released. Some of them are security fixes and must imperatively be released immediately because any delay leaves the customers at risk. Eventually upgrades to new versions are developed. Each release may potentially introduce a patent infringing change. In an ideal world legal analysis must be constantly done to keep the software non infringing on a timely basis.

The cumulative effect of all these constraints ensures that clearing all rights to one's own product is a practically impossible task. This is not a problem that can be solved with faster better search engines for patents and prior art. Even with perfect information on all the applicable patents and all relevant prior art the sheer number of patents and the frequency at which they must be verified are too great. The burden is mostly a function of arithmetic.

If software authors wish to be active participant in the marketplace they have no choice but to ignore patents and operate at the risk of infringing. The only alternative is to stop writing software. Mark Lemley describes this situation thus:63 (footnotes omitted)

This is a particular problem for semiconductor, telecommunications, and software companies, which must aggregate hundreds or thousands of different components to make an integrated product. Each of those components may be patented, some by many different people. The threat that any one of those patent owners can obtain an injunction shutting down the entire integrated product allows them to extort settlements well in excess of the value of their patent. The patent damages rules similarly permit excessive recoveries, such as the recent $1.5 billion jury verdict against Microsoft for infringing one of many patents covering just one of many features of an add-on to the Microsoft Windows product. Patent law permits these product manufacturers to be found to be "willful" infringers liable for treble damages and attorneys' fees, even if they were unaware of the patent or even the patent owner at the time they began selling the product. And even if the manufacturer can avoid any of these risks by invalidating or proving noninfringement of each of these patents, doing so will cost millions of dollars per case in legal fees. Given these problems, it's a wonder companies make products in patent-intensive industries at all.

And yet make products they do. Both my own experience and what limited empirical evidence there is suggest that companies do not seem much deterred from making products by the threat of all this patent litigation. Intel continues to make microprocessors, Cisco routers, and Microsoft operating system software, even though they collectively face nearly 100 patent-infringement lawsuits at a time and receive hundreds more threats of suit each year. Companies continue to do research on gene therapy, and even make "gene chips" that incorporate thousands of patented genes, despite the fact that a significant fraction of those genes are patented. Universities and academic researchers continue to engage in experimentation with patented inventions despite the now clear rule that they are not immune from liability for doing so. John Walsh's study suggests that threats of patent infringement are not in fact responsible for deterring much, if any, research.

What's going on here? The answer, I think, is straightforward, if surprising: both researchers and companies in component industries simply ignore patents. Virtually everyone does it.

...

To get a perspective on how strange this might seem to an outsider to the patent system--or even to an outsider to the component industries in which this behavior is common--compare it to the world of real property. If I want to build a house, I'd better be darn sure that I own the land on which the house is built. In fact, it would be foolhardy to begin construction before I owned the rights to the land, in the hopes that I would be able to obtain the rights later. Nor would a prospective homebuilder put up with significant uncertainty about the boundaries of the land on which she was building. People don't often build houses that might or might not be on their land, hoping that they would ultimately win any property dispute. And even if a few people were so reckless as to want to do one of these things, banks won't fund construction without certainty in the form of a title insurance search report indicating that the builder unambiguously owns all the rights she needs.

Mulligan and Lee further explain:64 (footnotes omitted)

The tendency to implicitly assume that economic actors are omniscient is a common pitfall of theoretical social science. By definition, the theorist knows everything there is to be known about the stylized model he has invented. Theorists often implicitly assume that economic actors automatically have the information they need to make decisions. Indeed, this may be essential to building a tractable model of the world. But the failure to ponder the feasibility of acquiring and using information can lead to flawed conclusions.

The contemporary patent debate suffers from just this blind spot. Each patent is a demand that the world refrain from practicing a claimed art without the patent holder's permission. Potential infringers can only comply with this demand if they are aware of the patent's existence. On a blackboard or in the pages of a law review article, it's easy to implicitly assume that everyone knows about every patent.

But the real world isn't so simple. To avoid infringement, a firm must expend resources to learn about potentially relevant patents. Typically this means hiring patent lawyers to conduct patent searches, which may or may not be affordable or effective. In this paper, we'll call the costs of such information-gathering activities the patent system's "discovery costs." One criterion for a well- functioning patent system-- or any system of property-like rights-- is that discovery costs should be low enough that it's economically feasible for firms to obtain the information they need to comply with the law.

Thinking explicitly about discovery costs is a powerful tool for understanding the dysfunctions of the patent system. As we will see, discovery costs are relatively low in pharmaceuticals and other chemical industries. As a consequence, the patent system serves these industries relatively well. In contrast, discovery costs in the software industry are so high that most firms don't even try to avoid infringement. Unsurprisingly, software is a major contributor to the recent spike in patent litigation.

This situation is not fostering innovation. It imposes an unreasonable burden on job creating businesses that sell actual products. The only businesses who can be sure of owning all software patent rights to their products are those which don't make actual software and prefer to sell and license patents. This situation promotes monopolistic licensing rents and litigation.

2. Litigation risks are a burden to community-based software development.

Sharing ideas among a group of people is a very effective way to develop software. Several models of organizations have been invented for this purpose.

On possible model is the free and open source model.65 People agree on a copyright license and share source code.66 Everyone can download, run, debug and improve the programs. The improvements are contributed back to the community. Very innovative and commercially important software is developed in this manner.67

Another model is the definition of communication protocols by the IETF. The formal definition of the process is centered around specification documents called RFCs (Request for Comments).68 But in practice the source code for reference implementation is also frequently shared.69 All the core protocols of the Internet have been invented and standardized in this manner.

The problem of patents for these groups is the same as for anyone else. They can't verify they don't infringe someone else's patents. These groups can agree among themselves on whatever agreement they need to share the rights and function as a group. But they can verify they won't infringe on the rights of outside parties. They must take the risk and find out the hard way if someone will sue. Either that or they don't write the software.

This problem may be more acute for these groups than it is for proprietary vendors because these development model don't permit to pinpoint any specific date where the code is released. Every contribution from every member must be shared publicly the very moment it is made if the group is to function as a group. Since members may contribute something anytime they please new code is constantly being published. Public repositories such as github are used for this purpose. Hence, there is no publication event before which it could make sense to perform a legal review of the code.

This situation is hindering innovation. These collaborative groups have invented very influential technologies. The working methods of these groups are themselves innovative. The legal risks imposed on these groups by software patents are real. On the other hand the benefits are non-existent. Their goal is to develop software, disclose their inventions and share them with the world. They do this without the incentive of exclusive rights and they don't hide anything as trade secrets. And they can't opt-out of the patent system because they can't opt-out of inadvertently infringing on someone else's patent and being sued.

3. In the computer programming art, patents provide low quality disclosure which is legally dangerous for a programmer to read.

For a programmer, reading patents is legally dangerous. He risks becoming liable for treble damages for willful infringement. There is no hope to mitigate this risk by clearing all the patent rights to the software for the reasons explained above. The only effective mitigation strategy is not to read patents. But then disclosure is ineffective because it is intended precisely to be read by the developers. Patent law cannot promote innovation according to its theory unless the disclosure is read by the practitioners of the art.

Many Groklaw members report that their employers forbid their developers from reading patents because the legal risks are high and there are no benefits. This phenomenon has been reported by Mark Lemley as well:70 (footnotes omitted)

[B]oth researchers and companies in component industries simply ignore patents. Virtually everyone does it. They do it at all stages of endeavor. Companies and lawyers tell engineers not to read patents in starting their research, lest their knowledge of the patent disadvantage the company by making it a willful infringer. Walsh et al., similarly find that much of the reason university researchers are not deterred by patents is that they never learn of the patent in the first place. When their research leads to an invention, their patent lawyers commonly don't conduct a search for prior patents before seeking their own protection in the Patent and Trademark Office (PTO). Nor do they conduct a search before launching their own product. Rather, they wait and see if any patent owner claims that the new product infringes their patent.
Software patents are not only ignored as a property system. They are also ignored as a source of knowledge.

For programmer the preferred form of disclosure is the source code of a well written working program. If the license allows the programmer to modify the program and distribute the modifications it is even better. Communities of developers in FOSS projects do this on a routine basis.

Software patents do not require the disclosure of source code. Please see Fonar Corporation v. General Electric Corporation.

As a general rule, where software constitutes part of a best mode of carrying out an invention, description of such a best mode is satisfied by a disclosure of the functions of the software. This is because, normally, writing code for such software is within the skill of the art, not requiring undue experimentation, once its functions have been disclosed. It is well established that what is within the skill of the art need not be disclosed to satisfy the best mode requirement as long as that mode is described. Stating the functions of the best mode software satisfies that description test. We have so held previously and we so hold today. Thus, flow charts or source code listings are not a requirement for adequately disclosing the functions of software.
See also Northern Telecom v. Datapoint Corporation:

The computer language is not a conjuration of some black art, it is simply a highly structured language … . The conversion of a complete thought (as expressed in English and mathematics, i.e. the known input, the desired output, the mathematical expressions needed and the methods of using those expressions) into a language a machine understands is necessarily a mere clerical function to a skilled programmer.
From the perspective of a programmer these cases eviscerate the usefulness of disclosure. The functions of most software inventions can be defined after a few brainstorming sessions. Turning these functions into a working implementation is still a lot of hard work. When only the functions are known, the programmer is still required to do the bulk of this work. But this obligation does not follow from the disclosure which is commonly available from FOSS projects.

The functions of existing software can usually be seen just by watching the program in action. Developers may watch over the shoulder of a user, or they may inspect the computer internals with debugging tools. Disclosing the functions of software without source doesn't disclose any trade secret.

The ineffectiveness of disclosure has been noted by some patent scholars. For example Benjamin Roin states:71 (footnotes omitted)

If the Supreme Court is correct that "the ultimate goal" of patent law is to facilitate the disclosure of information that would otherwise be kept secret, then our patent system appears to be in trouble. A number of empirical studies suggest that patent disclosures play an insignificant role in promoting R&D spillovers. This is partially a reflection of the basic economics of patenting, where companies typically patent only those inventions that are disclosed to the public through other channels. It also reflects the numerous alternative sources of information available to inventors. Both of these issues are largely inherent in the patent system.

Many of the other problems discussed in this Note are more amenable to repair, assuming the courts and policymakers genuinely wish to improve the disclosure value of patents. The Federal Circuit's willful infringement rules, for example, encourage innovators to protect themselves from treble damages by remaining "willfully ignorant" of the patents in their field. Many commentators have recommended abolishing the willfulness rules entirely, although the Federal Circuit appears wedded to the doctrine. Similarly, commentators have suggested that Congress remove the remaining loopholes in the publication rules for patent applications, which currently allow some of the most time-sensitive innovations to be both patented and withheld from the public. In industries where patent applications are thought to disclose too little knowledge, courts might require more detailed information about how to enable the claimed invention. In the software industry, for example, there might be a strong case for requiring patent applicants to disclose the source code of their program.

Until these issues are fixed there is no point for a programmer in reading patents. He takes a huge legal risk and most of the time he doesn't learn anything that wouldn't otherwise be known to him without much effort.

4. The normal costs/benefits analysis of patents is not applicable to software.

The usual costs/benefits analysis is based on the patent quid pro quo. The inventor is granted exclusive rights for a limited period of time in exchange of the disclosure of his invention. Then, according to theory, society benefits from the invention when the exclusive rights expire. But during this time period the patentee may recoup his investment. This incentive to innovate is viewed as more advantageous for society than forcing the inventor to protect his invention with trade secrets.

The table below summarizes this analysis of the costs and benefits of patents.

Benefits to Society

Costs to Society

Promotes progress of useful arts by rewarding inventors

Grant of exclusive rights to the invention for limited time

Supports the economy by encouraging innovation

Administrative costs (we need a Patent office)

Disclosure of what would otherwise be trade secrets

Legal costs such as liability for infringement and patent defense strategies

But in the case of software this analysis is not applicable. There are strong incentives to innovate other than patents. Software is protected by copyrights. Software authors have a strong first-mover advantage.72 Community-based development like FOSS amounts to free R&D to organizations who know how to keep a good relationship with a community. Also Community-based development inherently provides superior disclosure.

The table below shows how the costs and benefits of patents are applicable to software. This table is very different from the previous one.

Benefits to Society

Costs to Society

Promotes progress of software by rewarding inventors above and beyond the rewards already provided by copyrights, first mover advantage and community contribution to FOSS projects

Grant of exclusive rights to the invention for limited time

Supports the economy by encouraging innovation above and beyond the rewards already provided by copyrights, first mover advantage and community contribution to FOSS projects

Administrative costs (we need a Patent office)

Disclosure of what would otherwise be trade secrets above and beyond disclosure inherent to the release of source code by FOSS projects, but only to the extent readers don't fear being liable to treble damages for willful infringement

Legal costs such as liability for infringement and patent defense strategies

Software authors are unable to clear the rights to their own programs because it is not practically feasible to do so.

Harm to collaborative development such as FOSS limiting its positive contribution to progress, the economy and to disclosure of source code

Exclusive rights granted to the expressions of abstract ideas impinge on individual Free Speech rights

We cannot presume software patents are promoting innovation according to the normal costs/benefits analysis because this analysis is not applicable to software. There is no reason to believe an analysis which takes all relevant factor in consideration will show a positive contribution to society. In particular the inability of software authors to clear the rights to their own product strongly suggests that the costs far outweigh the benefits.

Conclusion

The fundamental problem of the patentability of software is that the Federal Circuit (and the CCPA before them) believes that the functions of software are performed through the physical properties of electrical circuits.73 This belief leads to the natural conclusion that software is an electrical process and software patents are not different from hardware patents. But programmers are not configuring circuits to take advantage of their physical properties. They are defining the meaning of organizations of data. They implement operations of arithmetic and logic which are applicable to this data based on its meaning.74 The legal view of software is based on a faulty understanding of computer programming.

The functions of software are performed through a combination of defining the meaning of data and giving input to an already implemented algorithm. Meaning is not a physical property of a circuit.75 Giving input to an algorithm is not configuring a machine structure.76 The consequence of the beliefs of the Federal Circuit is to treat as hardware patents what is actually patents on a certain category of expressions of ideas.

This treatment of software patents does not promote innovation because it cannot. Software patents do not actually practice any of the the principles of patent law that theoretically lead to innovation. The patent system cannot function as a property system for software because it is impossible for authors of software to be secure in their own property. Patent disclosure is not being read in practice because there is no reason for software authors to do so and plenty of reasons not to. In addition, the usual costs/benefits analysis of patents is not applicable. The incentive of patents to innovators overlaps with copyrights, FOSS and first mover advantage but their full costs and risks still accrue to the developers and society as a whole.

Software patents harm innovation because they encourage monopolistic rents and litigation.

The cure is simple, the courts should just admit the facts are as they are and apply the law accordingly. They should recognize that computations are expressions of ideas and stop conflating them with applications of ideas.

Not applying this cure will allow the problem to persist. This problem cannot be solved by improving the quality of prior art discovery and analysis. It cannot be solved by curtailing vague or overly broad claims. These improvements are welcome but they don't go to the point. We need to stop allowing patents on the meaning on symbols when they are dressed up as patents on hardware.

An approach based on semiotics would be a better interpretation of the law.77 This approach has the advantage of being neutral relative to technology. It is applicable whenever the claim recites a sign. Anything can be a sign if it is used as a sign. Therefore this approach is not limited to software. It is applicable (and limited) to whenever there is an issue of whether the subject matter of a claim is related to the meaning of a sign.

The semiotics approach avoids terms like "abstract idea" which are hard to define. It doesn't depend on whether the subject matter is mathematical or related to software. It relies on the well understood distinction between an expression and its meaning. It relies on the well understood notion that thoughts in the human mind are abstract ideas. It builds on established principles of law. It relies on the linguistic aspects of mathematics to define a clear boundary between abstract mathematical ideas and their applications which is consistent with Supreme Court precedents.78

There is no need to ask Congress to change the law. It is sufficient for the courts to acknowledge facts and interpret existing law accordingly.

Under this approach claims reciting software will be patentable when they claim a referent which is a patent-eligible invention. An industrial process for curing rubber such as the one in Diehr is patent-eligible. Inventions like remote surgery systems and anti-lock brake systems are patent-eligible when the referent is actually claimed and not merely referred to. Only claims directed to the expression of abstract ideas will be rejected. This is conforming with the theory that innovation is promoted by patents on the application of ideas but not by patents on the ideas themselves.

________________

1 The topics we propose in our response correspond to these sections as follows:

Suggested topic 1: Is computer software properly patentable subject matter?

Topic 1 is the main topic for the whole argument because the whole point of distinguishing between expressions and applications of ideas is to help determine the exact extent where a claim involving software should be patentable. Suggested topics 2, 3 and 4 each cover a particular aspect of this general topic.

Suggested topic 2: Are software patents helping or hurting the US innovation and hence the economy?

Topic 2 is discussed in section D. This topic is numerically listed in second place because of its importance. We discuss it last, in section D, because the flow of ideas works better logically when the reader has first seen the material presented in section A, B and C.

In this section we document how patents on the expressions of ideas in software break the assumptions underlying the operation of the patent system. Three broad categories of assumptions are broken. (1) The patent system cannot work as a property system because there is no way for software authors to clear all rights to their own properties. (2) Disclosure doesn't work because it is ineffective and legally dangerous to read. (3) The standard cost/benefit analysis motivating patents is inapplicable in this context.

None of these three categories of assumptions actually function according to theory. There is no reason to believe the patent system promote innovation because all arguments supporting this conclusion don't apply to how software patents actually work in practice.

Suggested topic 3: How can software developers help the courts and the USPTO understand how computers actually work so judges' decisions will match technical realities?

Topic 3 is split between sections A and B. Section A explains some principles of computer science while section B identifies errors and how they should be corrected.

The main theme underlying section A is that computers are machines for manipulating symbols which have meaning. Section A defines some terminology, like the vocabulary and concepts of semiotics. This section also explains some principles of computer science such as: (1) What is a mathematical algorithm. (2) How mathematics and algorithms relate to symbols and meaning. (3) How computers use algorithms. (4) What is the stored program architecture. Collectively these principles explain what is the role of expressions and meaning in computer science.

The main theme underlying section B is that computers don't perform their functions solely through their physical properties. They also depend on their semantical properties as is explained in section A. This is contrary to the legal view of software found in case law. The insistence that computer work solely through their physical properties negates the role of semantics in computer programming. This is the source of the conflation between expressions of ideas and application of ideas.

One of the errors is the artificial distinction between a printing process and a computing process which is discussed in our main response. Several other errors of this nature are also discussed in this supplement.

It doesn't help that case law never refers to the descriptions of what is a mathematical algorithm which are found in textbooks of mathematics. This leads to an incorrect distinction between 'mathematical' algorithms and those which are deemed 'non-mathematical'. This also prevents the courts from noticing the role of symbols and meaning in the mathematical foundations of computing.

Suggested topic 4: What is an abstract idea in software and how do expressions of ideas differ from applications of ideas?

Topic 4 is discussed in section C.

We argue that when the referent of symbols is not claimed their meaning is just a thought in the human mind. This suggests that the test for claims directed patent-ineligible abstract ideas should be patterned after the printed matter doctrine. The meaning of symbols must be given no patentable weight unless the referent is actually claimed.

2 Examples of such textbooks are:

Curry, Haskell B., Foundations of Mathematical Logic, Dover Publications, 1977, Revised and corrected reprint from McGraw Hill Book Company, Inc. 1963

Delong, Howard. A Profile of Mathematical Logic. Addison-Wesley Publishing Company. 1970. I use the September 1971 second printing. Reprints of this book are available from Dover Publications.

Epstein, Richard L., Carnielli, Walter A., Computability Computable Functions, Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, Wadsworth & Brooks/Cole, 1989, pages 63-71.

Kleene, Stephen Cole, Introduction to Metamathematics, D. Van Nostrand Company, 1952. I use the 2009 reprint by Ishi Press International 2009.

Kleene, Stephen Cole, Mathematical Logic, John Wiley & Sons, Inc. New York, 1967, reprint from Dover Publications 2002. pages 223-231.

3 See Rogers, Hartley Jr, Theory of Recursive Functions and Effective Computability, The MIT Press, 1987 pp. 1-2

4 See for instance textbooks on denotational semantics for one method of writing such descriptions. An example of such textbook is Stoy, Joseph E., Denotational Semantics: The Scott-Strachey Approach to Programming Language Theory, MIT Press, First Paperback Edition

5 See Curry supra, pages 1-3

; also see Ben-Ari, Mordechai, Mathematical Logic for Computer Science, Second Edition, Springer-Verlag, 2001, for a textbook on mathematical logic as it is applied to computer science.

6 Here are a few places where such descriptions may be found.

Boolos George S., Burgess, John P., Jeffrey, Richard C., Computability and Logic, Fifth Edition, Cambridge University Press, 2007, page 23-25.

Epstein, Richard L., Carnielli, Walter A., Computability Computable Functions, Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, Wadsworth & Brooks/Cole, 1989, pages 63-71.

Kleene, Stephen Cole, Mathematical Logic, John Wiley & Sons, Inc. New York, 1967, reprint from Dover Publications 2002. pages 223-231.

Kluge, Werner, Abstract Computing Machines, A Lambda Calculus Perspective , Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2005, pages 11-14.

Minsky, Marvin L., Computation, Finite and Infinite Machines , Prentice-Hall, 1967, pages 103-111

Stoltenberg-Hansen, Viggo, Lindström, Ingrid, Griffor, Edward R., Mathematical Theory of Domains , Cambridge University Press, 1994, pages 224-225.

7 See Stoltenberg-Hansen and al., supra, page 224.

8 See Stoltenberg-Hansen and al., supra, page 224.

9 See Boolos and al. supra, page 23.

10 See Boolos and al. supra, page 187.

11 See Epstein and al., supra, pages 65-66, quoting from Hermes, Enumerability, Decidability, Computability. 2nd ed., Springer Verlag 1969. "[W]e must be able to express the instructions for the execution of the process in a finitely long text." See also Stoltenberg-Hansen, Lindström and Griffor, supra, page 224. "[An algorithm] is a method or procedure which can be described in a finite way (a finite set of instructions)"

12 See Boolos and al. supra, pages 23.

13 See Stoltenberg-Hansen, Lindström and Griffor, supra, page 224. "[An algorithm] can be followed by someone or something to yield a computation solving each problem in [a class of problems]."

14 See Boolos and al. supra, pages 23-24.

15 See Kluge, supra, page 12.

16 See Stoltenberg-Hansen and al., supra, page 225.

17 This is Turing machines, general recursive functions and λ-calculus.

18 See Kluge, supra, page 12

19 See Kleene, supra, page 223.

20 See Epstein and al., supra, page 70.

21 A model of computation is a class of syntactic manipulations of symbols defined in terms of the permissible operations. Examples of models of computations are Turing-machines, λ-calculus and general recursive functions.

22 For a discussion of how problems are represented syntactically using symbols, see Greenlaw, Raymond, Hoover, H. James, Fundamentals of the Theory of Computation, Principles and Practice, Morgan Kaufmann Publishers, 1998, Chapter 2.

23 This is used during debugging. Programmers verify programs work as intended by reading the data stored in the computer memory. They interpret this information according to its logical data type to determine if the program implement the operations of arithmetic and logic that solves the problem.

24 See Poernomo, Iman Hafiz, Crossley, John Newsome, Wirsing, Martin, Adapting Proofs-as-Program, The Curry-Howard Protocol, Springer 2005. This thesis is presented in chapters 4, 5 and 6.

25 See Ben-Ari, supra, chapter 7 and 8 for a discussion of SLD-resolution.

26 See Kluge, supra, for a book dedicated to several implementations of normal order β -reduction. It should be noted that normal order β -reduction is a universal algorithm which modifies its program as the computation progresses. It cannot be assumed the program is always unchanged by the computation as is usually (but not always) the norm in imperative programming.

27 This is a simplified explanation for readability. Here is how Hamacher, V. Carl, Vranesic, Zvonko G., Zaky. Safwat G., describes the hardware implementation of an instruction cycle. See Computer organization, Fifth Edition, McGraw-Hill Inc. 2002 p. 43 (emphasis in the original)

Let us consider how this program is executed. The processor contains a register called the program counter (PC) which holds the address of the instruction to be executed next. To begin executing a program, the address of its first instruction (i in our example) must be placed into the PC. Then, the processor control circuits use the information in the PC to fetch and execute instructions, one at a time, in the order of increasing addresses. This is called straight-line sequencing. During the execution of each instruction, the PC is incremented by 4 to point to the next instruction. Thus, after the Move instruction at location i + 8 is executed the PC contains the value i + 12 which is the address of the first instruction of the next program segment.

Executing a given instruction is a two-phase procedure. In the first phase, called instruction fetch, the instruction is fetched from the memory location whose address is in the PC. This instruction is placed in the instruction register (IR) of the processor. At the start of the second phase, called instruction execute, the instruction in IR is examined to determine which operation to be performed. The specified operation is then performed by the processor. This often involve fetching operands from the memory or from processor registers, performing an arithmetic or logic operation, and storing the result in the destination location. At some point during this two-phase procedure, the contents of the PC are advanced to point at the next instruction. When the execute phase of an instruction is completed, the PC contains the address of the next instruction, and a new instruction fetch phase can begin.

28 A suitable analogy may be travel directions. These instructions don't drive the car. They are input given to the driver.

29 See section A.3, supra. Section A.2 explains the relationship between algorithms, formulas and equations. These two sections explain the mathematical meaning of all terms which have troubled the Federal Circuit in AT&T Corporation.

30 See Milner, Robin, Tofte, Mads, Harper, Robert, MacQueen, David, The Definition of Standard ML (Revised) , The MIT Press, 1997, for the official definition of the Standard ML language. See also Reppy, John H., Concurrent Programming in ML, Cambridge University Press, First published 1999, Digitally printed version (with corrections) 2007, appendix B, for the official definition of the Concurrent ML extensions.

31 See section A.3 supra.

32 Cybersource Corporation vs Retail Decisions, Inc. sounds like a possible example of this argument. They write "That purely mental processes can be unpatentable, even when performed by a computer, was precisely the holding of the Supreme Court in Gottschalk v. Benson." And then they continue writing "This is entirely unlike cases where, as a practical matter, the use of a computer is required to perform the claimed method." Benson is the case which established the mathematical algorithm exception. To the extent that ordinary logic is applicable here, one may conclude the Federal Circuit in Cybersource said the mathematical algorithm exception is not applicable when the use of a computer is required as a practical matter to perform the claimed method. Mathematicians have deliberately decided to ignore this kind of distinction when they defined their notion of algorithm.

33 See section A.4 supra.

34 This is unless we count artificial intelligence programs such as IBM's Watson as being able to relate the syntax of human language with its meaning. No matter how we look at this issue, there is no factual difference between a printing press and a computer instruction cycle. If we consider computers as unable to understand meaning they are no better than printing presses. But if they are able to understand meaning printed information is not intelligible only by a human being. Either way the guidance offered by Lowry doesn't apply to the facts.

35 See section A.4 supra

36 An alternative version of the change to the machine structure argument has been stated in WMS Gaming vs International Game technology:

The instructions of the software program that carry out the algorithm electrically change the general purpose computer by creating electrical paths within the device. These electrical paths create a special purpose machine for carrying out the particular algorithm.[3]

______________

[Footnote 3]: A microprocessor contains a myriad of interconnected transistors that operate as electronic switches. See Neil Randall, Dissecting the Heart of Your Computer, PC Magazine, June 9, 1998, at 254-55. The instructions of the software program cause the switches to either open or close. See id. The opening and closing of the interconnected switches creates electrical paths in the microprocessor that cause it to perform the desired function of the instructions that carry out the algorithm. See id.

This alternative explanation is immediately refuted because it is manifestly false. A stored program computer is programmed by storing the instructions in main memory. This action doesn't create electrical paths because main memory doesn't work in this manner. Main memory is a component that merely records information. On modern DRAM technology this information is electric charges stored in capacitors. No transistors are opened and closed to create electric paths in the microprocessor when these electric charges are stored.

Programs are not stored in the microprocessor mentioned in the footnote because this component is not main memory. The activity of the transistors turning on and off in the microprocessor is the execution of the program. Programming a computer and executing a program are two separate actions. It is an error to conflate them as the court do in WMS Gaming.

The instructions that could be executed by a microprocessor are very elementary. A complete algorithm typically requires a large number of these rudimentary instructions. Complete programs require thousands or even millions of instructions. On the other hand a microprocessor typically executes the instructions one by one. In some microprocessors gains of speed are achieved by executing a very small quantity of instructions in parallel when it is feasible to do so. Microprocessor execute large number of instructions by executing on them in successive cycles, one (or a few) instruction(s) per cycle. The transistors turning on and off are the execution of this small number of instructions and different electrical paths are created in each cycle. No electric paths for carrying out a particular algorithm is created because the number of instructions which are executed in a single cycle is too small.

See section A.5 supra for a discussion of the instruction cycle.

37 In mathematics this partial application of the parameters of a mathematical function is called currying.

38 These function are not special cases of multiplication. We can double a number by adding it with itself. This shows that doubling is a concept independent from multiplication because we can implement it without multiplying. Similarly we can triple a number by adding it with itself twice. Adding the number with itself three times quadruple the number.

39 Here is another way to illustrate the relationship between meaning and machine. Please recall the claim about a printing press configured to make marks of ink of paper telling the story of hobbits traveling in faraway countries to destroy an evil anvil. It was mentions in section B.3 supra.

We may argue that a configured printing press is different from an unconfigured printing press. Different books are different articles of manufacture. The marks of ink on paper will not be arranged in the same manner. Therefore printing presses configured for different books will perform different functions because they don't manufacture the same article. This means a printing press configured to print a book is a different machine than a printing press without the configuration. One may print the stated book while the other can't. Also, the configured printing press is physically different from the unconfigured one because some of its elements are differently arranged.

This argument repeats the typical justifications of the doctrine that programming a computer makes a machine different from the unprogrammed computer. The correspondence is complete when we consider that a printing press may be controlled by an embedded programmed microprocessor and a computer may be connected to a printer. In section B.3 we argued there are no factual differences between a printing press and a computer that would justify a applying the printed matter doctrine to a configured printing press but not to a programmed computer. Now we make the same observation about the "makes a different machine" doctrine.

While we argue the printed matter doctrine should apply to both types of devices, we argue the "makes a different machine" doctrine should apply to neither.

40 In some cases the configuration can be made permanent by storing it in memory types such as ROM that can't be overwritten. However typical software patents are not limited to this type of memory. They will read on implementations using the more commonly used writable memory.

41 Remember that it is not possible to define this process in terms of the meaning of the data.

42 Without such an argument his position would immediately be refuted by the observation that main memory changes up to billions of times per second.

43 Let's consider, for example, what happens when we store instructions for a x86 CPU on a SPARC workstation. The SPARC uses a different instruction set than the x86. A program for a x86 computer does not normally run on a SPARC workstation. But a SPARC can execute the Bochs program which is a software version of the x86 instruction cycle. If this program is used the x86 program will run on a SPARC. This shows that instructions by themselves are just a series of numbers in memory. They don't impart functionality unless and until they are given as input to an algorithm which is the instruction cycle.

44 Please remember that several programing languages use a software universal algorithm. They don't directly use the computer native instruction cycle. See section A.5 supra.

45 The extreme case occurs with self-modifying programs. In a stored program computer all data in memory may be modified as the program is executed. Programmers may arrange their programs so that they are modified in memory as they are executed. Then the alleged "machine configuration" doesn't stay in place long enough to perform all the steps that are necessary to infringe on the patent claim. A simple way to achieve this result is to use a programming language with relies on a variant of normal order β-reduction as its universal algorithm. (See section A.5 supra.) This particular category of universal algorithms constantly modifies its program as it executes. This is done automatically by the language run-time system without any action of the part of the programmer other than his decision to program in this language.

46 See section B.2 supra.

47 An example of a symbol is a letter in the common Latin alphabet. A letter may be a mark of in on paper, a carving in stone, the shape of a neon sign, an arrangement of pixels on the screen. A letter come in different shapes depending on typefaces. These are different physical objects separate from the abstraction called a letter. This concept of 'symbol' as an abstraction separate from its representation is explicitly acknowledged in mathematical logic and computation theory. See for instance Curry, supra, pages 15-16.

In the theory presented here, one may conceive such assumptions as entering in certain abstractions. The first of these is involved in the use of such terms as 'symbol' and 'expression'; these denote, not individual marks on paper or the blackboard--which are called inscriptions--but classes of such inscriptions which are "equiform." Thus the same expressions may have several "occurrences."

48 See section A.1. The approach suggested here has been proposed in Collins, Kevin Emerson, Semiotics 101: Taking the Printed Matter Doctrine Seriously (February 28, 2009). Indiana Law Journal, Vol. 85, p. 1379, 2010. Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1351066. We don't agree with everything Collins say because he did not recognize the errors we have mentioned in section B. We believe that once these errors are corrected his approach is correct.

49 See section A.4 supra.

50 This is the thesis of Kevin Emerson Collins in his article quoted supra.

51 See the criteria of "precise definition" for the mathematical notion of algorithm in section A.3 supra.

52 See section B.2 supra.

53 See sections B.1 and B.2, supra.

54 See sections B.3 and footnote 39, supra.

55 See section B.4, supra.

56 See sections B.5 and B.6, supra.

57 See section A.4, supra.

58 See Lemley, Mark A., Software Patents and the Return of Functional Claiming (July 25, 2012). Stanford Public Law Working Paper No. 2117302. Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2117302 or http://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2117302 pages 24-25.

59 See Mulligan, Christina and Lee, Timothy B., Scaling the Patent System (March 6, 2012). NYU Annual Survey of American Law, Forthcoming. Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract_id=2016968.

60 See Mulligan and Lee, supra, pp. 16-17

61 See Mulligan and Lee, supra, p. 7.

62 See Mulligan and Lee, supra, p. 6.

In the real world, lawyers frequently cannot state for certain whether a given activity actually infringes a particular patent. In this paper, we will largely set this issue to the side and assume counterfactually that lawyers can always determine whether a particular activity infringes a particular patent in a reasonable amount of time. For further reading on the challenges of claim construction and determining the scope of patents, see Jeanne Fromer, Claiming Intellectual Property, 76 U. CHI. L. REV. 719 (2009), Michael Risch, The Failure of Public Notice in Patent Prosecution, 21 HARV. J. L. & TECH. 179 (2007); Christopher A. Cotropia, Patent Claim Interpretation Methodologies and their Claim Scope Paradigms, 47 WM. & MARY L. REV 49 (2005); Christopher A. Cotropia, Patent Claim Interpretation and Information Costs, 9 LEWIS & CLARK L. REV. 57 (2005).

63 See Lemley, Mark A., Ignoring Patents (July 3, 2007). Stanford Public Law Working Paper No. 999961; Michigan State Law Review, Vol. 2008, No. 19, 2008. Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=999961 or http://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.999961 pages 19-21.

64 See Mulligan and Lee, supra, pp 2-4.

65 A description of what is free software is maintained by the Free Software Foundation. The Open Source Initiative maintains the definition of open source software.

66 The Free Software Foundation maintains a list of licenses which are accepted for free software development. The Open Source Initiative also maintains their list of licenses for open source software.

67 The most famous example is the Linux operating system kernel. It is at the core of several operating systems such as GNU/Linux and Android. We may also mention the Perl and Python programming languages, the Coq proof assistant, web browsers such as Firefox and Chrome and also the Apache web server. This list far from exhaustive.

68 See RFC 2026 for the current version of the RFC development process. RFC 2555 is an historic account describing how the RFC process has been used to invent and disclose the core Internet protocols.

69 An example of a reference implementation is found in RFC 1321 Appendix A. Reference implementations may also be incorporated by reference. For example RFC 5905 includes the reference "This document includes material from [ref9], which contains flow charts and equations unsuited for RFC format. There is much additional information in [ref7], including an extensive technical analysis and performance assessment of the protocol and algorithms in this document. The reference implementation is available at www.ntp.org." This same RFC 5905 also includes a skeleton program with code segments in appendix A.

70 See Lemley, Mark A., Ignoring Patents (July 3, 2007). Stanford Public Law Working Paper No. 999961; Michigan State Law Review, Vol. 2008, No. 19, 2008. pages 21-22.

Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=999961 or http://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.999961

71 Benjamin Roin, Note, The Disclosure Function of the Patent System (Or Lack Thereof), 118 HARV. L. REV. 2007 (2005) (noting that the patent system doesn't achieve this disclosure goal). Available at: http://hlr.rubystudio.com/issues/118/april05/Note_3857.php

72 Eric Goldman explains this first mover advantage in term of the soft life-cycle of software. (See Goldman, Eric, Fixing Software Patents (January 1, 2013). Forbes Tertium Quid Blog, November 28, December 11 and December 12, 2012; Santa Clara Univ. Legal Studies Research Paper No. 01-13. Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2199180 page 2)

Software innovators can recoup some of their R&D investments from the de facto marketplace exclusivity associated with being the first mover. An example: assume that a particular software innovation has a two-year commercial lifecycle and it takes competitors 6 months to bring a matching product to market. In a situation like this, the first mover gets 1/4 of the maximum useful exclusivity period simply by being first to market. In some situations, the exclusivity period provided by the first mover advantage is more than enough to motivate software R&D without any patent protection.

73 See section B generally, especially the quote from In re Noll in section B.6, supra..

74 See section A.3 and A.4, supra.

75 See section B generally, especially sections B.3, B.4, B.5 and B.6, supra.

76 See section B.5, supra.

77 This is the approach we have described in section C.2, supra.

78 See section B.4, supra.


  View Printable Version


Groklaw © Copyright 2003-2013 Pamela Jones.
All trademarks and copyrights on this page are owned by their respective owners.
Comments are owned by the individual posters.

PJ's articles are licensed under a Creative Commons License. ( Details )